Abstract

With the use of only the incidence axioms we prove and generalize Desargues’ two-triangle Theorem in three-dimensional projective space considering an arbitrary number of points on each one of the two distinct planes allowing corresponding points on the two planes to coincide and three points on any of the planes to be collinear. We provide three generalizations and we define the notions of a generalized line and a triangle-connected plane set of points.

1. The Problem in Perspective

Perhaps the most important proposition deduced from the axioms of incidence in projective geometry for the projective space is Desargues’ two-triangle Theorem usually stated quite concisely as follows:

two triangles in space are perspective from a point if and only if they are perspective from a line

meaning that if we assume a one-to-one correspondence among the vertices of the two triangles, then the lines joining the corresponding vertices are concurrent if and only if the intersections of the lines of the corresponding sides are collinear (Figure 1). According to the ancient Greek mathematician Pappus (3rd century A.D.), this theorem was essentially contained in the lost treatise on Porisms of Euclid (3rd century B.C.) [1, 2] but it is nowadays known by the name of the French mathematician and military engineer Gerard Desargues (1593–1662) who published it in 1639. Actually only half of it is called Desargues’ Theorem (perspectivity from a point implies perspectivity from a line) whereas the other half is called converse of Desargues’ Theorem. All printed copies of Desargues’ treatise were lost, but fortunately Desargues’ contemporary French mathematician Phillipe de La Hire (1640–1718) made a manuscript copy of it which was discovered again some 200 years later [3].

There exist a few hidden assumptions in the above pretty and compact statement of the theorem. Namely, all mentioned lines and intersection points are assumed to exist and the three points on each plane are assumed to be noncollinear. It seems that in bibliography there exist very few treatments of the theorem paying attention to these assumptions, like Hodge and Pedoe’s [4] and Pogorelov’s [5]. The purpose of this paper is to deal with these assumptions. It is also worth mentioning that Desargues was interested in triangles in space formed by intersecting two distinct planes with three lines going through a common point. Remarkably, although the theorem remains true even when the two planes of the projective space coincide, it is not at all evident that it holds whenever we work solely in a general projective plane disregarding a larger surrounding projective space. Actually Desargues’ Theorem does not hold in the projective geometry of a general projective plane defined by the usual incidence axioms as Hilbert has shown [6], unless if the theorem itself or a statement that implies it is assumed as an axiom. Such a set of axioms was given by Bachmann [7], and a proof of Desargues’ Theorem can be found in [8] based on the following Pappus’ Theorem of Euclidean Geometry being considered as an axiom:

if the six vertices of a hexagon lie alternatively on two lines, then the three points of intersection of pairs of opposite sides are collinear.

The general projective planes came to existence in an attempt to construct via incidence axioms planes in which Desargues’ Theorem does or rather does not hold. They are defined as collections of two kinds of objects called points and lines satisfying at least the following three incidence axioms:(i)any two distinct points are incident with exactly one line;(ii)any two distinct lines are incident with exactly one point;(iii)there exist four points of which no three are collinear,where incidence is used as a neutral word meaning that the point belongs or lies on the line and also meaning that the line passes through or contains the point. Collinearity has the usual meaning. Some projective planes have only finitely many points and lines whereas some others have infinitely many. Desargues’ Theorem fails to hold for many of them, both finite and infinite [912]. Hilbert [6], Hall [13], and others have proved a plane is Desarguesian (for such planes Desargues’ Theorem holds) if and only if it can be constructed algebraically from the vector spaces over the division rings , where the points of these planes are just the lines of the vector space and the lines of the planes are the subspaces of spanned by two linearly independent vectors of it. The usual real projective plane comes by this construction from .

Nevertheless, for projective spaces of dimension at least three which are defined similar to the projective planes either by a set of incidence axioms or by algebraic constructions, Desargues’ Theorem is always true [4]. These higher dimensional projective spaces contain 2-dimensional projective planes and it is easily seen that Desargues’ Theorem holds for all such projective planes too.

We are going to prove and generalize Desargues’ Theorem working in a three-dimensional projective space and considering an arbitrary number of points on each one of the two distinct planes, allowing some of the lines and intersection points mentioned in the above statement of the theorem to disappear. For this matter we will allow some of the given points on one of the planes to coincide with their corresponding points on the other plane. Also, although we will always be assuming that the given points are distinct on each plane, we will drop the restriction that any three of them are noncollinear. All our proofs will be based directly on the axioms of projective geometry in space and their immediate corollaries.

The projective space we will be working on consists of three kinds of objects called points, lines, and planes for which the following incidence axioms hold [5]:(i)there exists exactly one line through any two distinct points;(ii)any two distinct lines on the same plane have a unique common point;(iii)there exist at least three points on each line;(iv)there exist three points not on the same line;(v)there exist four points not on the same plane;(vi)there exists exactly one plane through any three distinct noncollinear points; there exists at least one point on each plane;(vii)if two distinct points are on a plane, then all points in the line containing the given points are on the same plane;(viii)if two planes have a common point, then they have at least one more common point. Some immediate corollaries are the following:(i)a plane and a line not on the plane always have a unique common point;(ii)two distinct planes intersect in a common line.A number of given points will be called collinear whenever some line contains all of them (if some points coincide, there may be more than one such line). Similarly, a number of given lines will be called concurrent whenever there exists at least one point lying on all of them. We will say a given set of points on a plane is in general position whenever no three collinear points exist among them. A usual triangle or just a triangle will be a triad of lines defined by three noncollinear points.

2. A Generalized Desargues’ Theorem for Points in General Position Allowing Corresponding Points to Coincide

Figure 2(a) makes it clear that if we wish to generalize to larger numbers of points the converse of Desargues’ Theorem, we have to assume distinct given points on each plane. Similarly, Figure 2(b) says that we should not allow some three collinear points on a plane whenever some of the rest coincide with their corresponding points on the other plane. Nevertheless there do exist generalizations if we allow only one of these two bothersome situations to happen, as we show below.

So let be given points on a plane and some corresponding points on another plane allowing for the possibility that some corresponding points coincide. Instead of ignoring pairs of coinciding corresponding points we choose to use generalized lines defining a generalized line to be the line through and whenever are distinct, otherwise to be the set of all lines through as this seems most natural. It is also convenient to say that contains or goes through all points in our projective space. Our first generalization is the following (Figure 3).

Proposition 1. Let be two distinct planes, , , distinct points on , and distinct points on , both sets of points in general position.
(A) If all generalized lines go through a common point, then all the intersections of the pairs of lines for are nonempty and lie on a common line (the common line of and ).
(B) If all the intersections of the pairs of lines for are nonempty, then all generalized lines go through a common point.

Proof. For part (A) holds vacuously. For note that for arbitrary distinct indices the generalized lines and share some common point; thus the lines should lie on some common plane (Figure 4 provides a quick pictorial proof) and so they should have a nonempty intersection. But the first of these lines belongs to whereas the second belongs to which forces their intersection to lie on , the common line of the distinct planes . Since this happens for all indices we are finished with part (A).
The proof of part (B) is a bit longer. For the proposition holds vacuously. For its truth is immediate whenever at least one of the generalized lines is not a line, whereas if both of them are lines, they either coincide (both with the common line of and ) and the results hold trivially, or else they are distinct, in which case the four points do not lie on the same line. But then the lines are also distinct, and as their intersection is nonempty by assumption, they define a plane on which lie the points forcing the lines to lie on this plane too and thus to have nonempty intersection (a single point, since these lines do not coincide).
For and assuming that at least one of the generalized lines is not a line, say , the result comes from the truth of case , since have to share some common point which of course lies on the generalized line as well. So assume that all three of these generalized lines are lines (Figure 1), which is the classical assumption for the converse of Desargues’ Theorem.
Observe that at least one of the points , say , does not lie on ; otherwise the plane defined by these three noncollinear points would coincide with , which cannot happen. Then the line does not lie on either, and so it is distinct from the line which lies on , and since have a nonempty intersection, they define a plane, say . The line cannot lie on for if it did, the three noncollinear points would lie on making it coincide with , and then point of would be a point of , a contradiction. So the line has a unique common point with . And we show below that has a unique intersection point with either of lines of . Therefore have to go through a common point as wanted. Now for the claim about the intersections of with , the lines are distinct; otherwise the lines would coincide forcing to lie on which it cannot do. Then since by hypothesis intersect nonvacuously they define a plane on which all four points lie, making the lines lie on it and so have a nonempty intersection. This intersection is actually a unique point; otherwise the lines would coincide forcing to lie on , a contradiction. Quite similarly intersects in a unique point as wanted.
For there exist at least lines among the ’s for, if not, at least three ’s would coincide with the corresponding ’s, and all these would be collinear lying on the common line of and contrary to the proposition’s assumption.
If there exist exactly two lines among the ’s (which can happen only for ), say and , then for the points and coincide and lie on the common line of . Now the lines cannot coincide; otherwise they would lie on both , and so they would coincide with ; thus all points would lie on , contrary to our original assumption. Since are distinct and by assumption intersect nonvacuously, they define a plane on which lie all four points . So both lines lie on this plane as well, and they must have a nonempty intersection, a single point. Of course all generalized lines go through this point as well.
Finally, if there exist at least three lines among the ’s, say with , then according to the proof of case , for any , the lines , and are distinct and intersect each other in a single point which makes all three of them go through a common point, say . Since is the unique common point of the distinct lines (see scholium below) for all indices , all these points coincide and the lines go through this common point, which of course is also a point of any generalized as wanted, finishing the proof of the proposition.

Remark 2. The above proof reveals that with the classical hypothesis for the converse of Desargues’ Theorem the three lines are distinct and the three planes defined by two of them at a time are distinct, a result to be used in the next section. Indeed, with the assumptions made in the proof, line is distinct from the other two since it does not lie on the plane defined by them, whereas if were not distinct, the points would lie on the same line and this line would be of course , forcing to lie on and therefore on , a contradiction. And any two of the planes defined by two of have to be distinct since otherwise all points would lie on the same plane forcing and to coincide, which cannot be.

3. A Generalization for the Converse of Desargues’ Theorem for Triangle-Connected Given Points

The assumptions postulated in part (B) of Proposition 1 can be considerably relaxed. For example, there is no reason for assuming that all lines intersect with their corresponding lines , since a much smaller number of lines among the ’s with the same property force all the rest to behave similarly.

This is made clear in Figure 5 where the lines of the sides of triangle intersect their corresponding lines of triangle making the lines go through the same point , and similarly the lines of the sides of triangle intersect their corresponding lines of triangle making the lines go through the same point . Since both coincide with the intersection point of and they have to coincide with each other, thus making all lines go through a common point. Then by part (A) of Proposition 1, lines have to intersect as well. Of course all the intersections of the pairs of lines have to lie on the common line of and .

Also note that the points , and need not be noncollinear by three; in the argument above we only needed the existence of the triangles and and their corresponding ones in . Finally note that if we expand the given sets of points with some more points all in the common line of and , then trivially all lines continue to share a common point.

This argument extends similarly for any given points and on the two planes. All we need is to assume that all points that do not coincide with their corresponding points are similarly triangle-connected on the two planes. The meaning of this should be rather clear.

A triangle-connection sequence in or for simplicity just triangle-connection sequence for two points of a given set will be any finite sequence of triangles formed by lines through the points of so that any two consecutive triangles share a common side and belongs to the first triangle of this sequence whereas belongs to the last one; recall from Section 1 that a triangle is a set of three lines. A triangle-connection set for will be a set of triangle-connection sequences of points of , that contains exactly one such sequence for each pair of points of . Of course whenever such a set exists for , it is not necessarily unique. The triangles in the sequences of such a set will be called connection triangles for and the lines of the sides connection lines. Two given sets of points and on two planes where corresponds to will be called similarly triangle-connected whenever there exists a triangle-connection set for the ’s which becomes a triangle-connection set for the ’s by replacing all vertices of all triangles in the sequences of this set by their corresponding points on the other plane.

For example, a triangle-connection set for the set in Figure 6(a) is , where and triangles are denoted by the three names of their vertices. The triangle-connection lines in this set are and , that is, lines in total. It is interesting to note by the way that the minimum number of connection lines in a triangle-connection set of lines for given points no three of which are collinear is . Figure 6(b) hints at the reason; a rigorous proof is easy to come by.

Now for two similarly triangle-connected sets of points and on two planes and and assuming to be a connection triangle on one of the planes, we know by the remark after Proposition 1 that the lines are distinct and that all three intersect in a single point . It is quite trivial to show, and we do so in the next paragraph, that every line intersects all three lines nonvacuously for all . Since, for , the line does not belong to at least one of the distinct planes defined by and , we get that has a unique point with at least one of the planes. In other words either intersects and of the first of these planes on their common point or else intersects and of the second plane on their common point . So all lines go through proving Proposition 3 below, which is a generalization of the converse of Desargues’ Theorem.

About the claim that for all the line intersects nonvacuously all three lines , for this is immediate, so consider an so that is a usual line and choose a triangle-connection sequence for and . For any triangle in this sequence and its corresponding on the other plane, the assumptions for the converse of the classical Desargues Theorem are satisfied so (see the scholium) the lines are distinct and all three intersect in a single point. Now for two such consecutive triangles the two concurrency points are the same since they both coincide with the unique intersection point of and . This implies that all lines for all the vertices of all triangles in these triangle-connection sequences have to go through a common point, which implies and have some common point. Similarly, intersects and as well and we are done.

Proposition 3. Let be two distinct planes, distinct points on , and distinct points on where are considered to be corresponding. Assume that for the given points on the two planes which do not coincide with their corresponding points there exist similar triangle-connection sets so that every pair of corresponding triangle-connection lines has a nonempty intersection. Then all generalized lines go through a common point. Moreover, all pairs of lines for intersect nonvacuously (on the common line of and ).

The existence of the triangle-connection sets guarantees that and that at least three points on each of the planes do not coincide with their corresponding points on the other. If exactly two points on each plane do not coincide with their corresponding points, then all but two lines are generalized but the remaining two are not guaranteed to have a nonempty intersection and thus this case cannot be included to the proposition.

4. Whenever Three or More Collinear Points Are Allowed but Corresponding Points Are Assumed Distinct

We close with a third generalization of the converse of Desargues’ Theorem. In Proposition 1 the given points on the two planes were allowed to coincide with their corresponding points, but no three given points on any of the planes were allowed to be collinear. Flipping over these assumptions and restrictions, we now forbid any two corresponding points to coincide but allow three or more of them on any of the planes to be collinear. Figure 7 reveals that the converse of Desargues’ Theorem does not always hold then; at least it does not hold whenever the given points on the planes are all collinear. Interestingly enough, it does hold whenever the given points on one of the planes do not all lie in a single line.

Proposition 4. Let be two distinct planes, , distinct points on , and distinct points on so that for all . If all intersections are nonempty and not all of the given points are collinear on at least one of the given planes, then all lines go through a common point.

Proof. For this is exactly part (B) of Proposition 1. Similarly, it is part (B) of Proposition 1 whenever and no three collinear points exist among the given ones in any of the planes. For and assuming to be collinear on , then does not lie on the line of the other three and so are usual nontrivial triangles, the points are triangle-connected, and our proposition holds because of Proposition 3.
Finally, for , we proceed inductively assuming the result holds for all : by the proposition’s assumptions we can consider to be not all collinear. If all but one of them are collinear, say not on the line of the rest, then form a triangle-connection set for the ’s and the result follows from Proposition 3.
If on the other hand no more than of the ’s are collinear, choose two of them, say , not on the common line of . Now observe that the two sets of in number points and satisfy the assumptions of the proposition; thus by our induction hypothesis the result holds for them. In other words, all lines go through a common point of and similarly all lines go through a point of . But points coincide because the lines are distinct: if not, would coincide with because they would be the line of and at the same time the line of ; this would make points of , a contradiction. So all lines go through and we are done.

Conflict of Interests

The author declares that there is no conflict of interests regarding the publication of this paper.