Abstract

There are five equivalence relations known as Green's relations definable on any semigroup or monoid, that is, on any algebra with a binary operation which is associative. In this paper, we examine whether Green's relations can be defined on algebras of any type 𝜏. Some sort of (super-)associativity is needed for such definitions to work, and we consider algebras which are clones of terms of type 𝜏, where the clone axioms including superassociativity hold. This allows us to define for any variety 𝑉 of type 𝜏 two Green's-like relations 𝑉 and 𝑉 on the term clone of type 𝜏. We prove a number of properties of these two relations, and describe their behaviour when 𝑉 is a variety of semigroups.

1. Introduction

A semigroup is an algebra of type (2) for which the single binary operation satisfies the associativity identity. A monoid is a semigroup with an additional nullary operation which acts as an identity element for the binary operation. On any semigroup or monoid, the five equivalence relations known as Green's relations provide information about the structure of the semigroup.

To define Green's relations on a semigroup 𝒜, we follow the convention of denoting the binary operation of the semigroup by juxtaposition. For any elements 𝑎 and 𝑏 of 𝐴, we say that 𝑎𝐴𝑏 if and only if 𝑎=𝑏 or there exist some 𝑐 and 𝑑 in 𝐴 such that 𝑐𝑎=𝑏 and 𝑑𝑏=𝑎. When the semigroup 𝒜 is clear from the context, we usually omit the superscript 𝐴 on the name of the relation 𝐴 and just write 𝑎𝑏. Dual to this “left” relation is the “right” relation defined by 𝑎𝑏 if and only if 𝑎=𝑏 or there exist 𝑐 and 𝑑 in 𝐴 such that 𝑎𝑐=𝑏 and 𝑏𝑑=𝑎. Both and are equivalence relations on any semigroup 𝒜. The remaining Green's relations are =, 𝒟= o = o , and 𝒥, defined by 𝑎𝒥𝑏 if and only if 𝑎=𝑏 or there exist elements 𝑐, 𝑑, 𝑝 and 𝑞 in 𝐴 such that 𝑎=𝑐𝑏𝑑 and 𝑏=𝑝𝑎𝑞. For more information about Green's relations in general, we refer the reader to [1].

In this paper, we consider how one might extend the definitions of the five Green's relations to algebras of any arbitrary type. In Section 2, we propose some definitions for and , and show what properties are needed to make our relations into equivalence relations. Then we consider a variation which extends our definition of two relations and to relations 𝑉 and 𝑉 on the term clone of any variety 𝑉. In Section 3, we deduce a number of properties of these two relations, and then in Section 4 we examine their behaviour when 𝑉 is a variety of semigroups.

2. Green's Relations for Any Type

We begin with some notation. Throughout this paper, we will assume a type 𝜏=(𝑛𝑖)𝑖𝐼, with an 𝑛𝑖-ary operation symbol 𝑓𝑖 for each index 𝑖 in some set 𝐼. For each 𝑛1, we let 𝑋𝑛={𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛} be an 𝑛-element alphabet of variables, and let 𝑊𝜏(𝑋𝑛) be the set of all 𝑛-ary terms of type 𝜏. Then we set 𝑋={𝑥1,𝑥2,𝑥3,}, and let 𝑊𝜏(𝑋) denote the set of all (finitary) terms of type 𝜏. Terms can be represented by tree diagrams called semantic trees. We will use the well-known Galois connection Id-Mod between classes of algebras and sets of identities. For any class 𝐾 of algebras of type 𝜏 and any set Σ of identities of type 𝜏, Mod Σ is the class of all algebras 𝒜 of type 𝜏 which satisfy all the identities in Σ, while Id𝐾 is the set of all identities 𝑠𝑡 of type 𝜏 which are satisfied by all algebras in 𝐾.

As a preliminary step in defining Green's relations on any algebra of arbitrary type, let us consider first the case of type 𝜏=(𝑛), where we have a single operation symbol 𝑓 of arity 𝑛1. In analogy with the two left and right Green's relations and for type (2), we can define 𝑛 different Green's-like relations here. Let 𝒜 be an algebra of type (𝑛) and let 𝑎 and 𝑏 be elements of 𝐴. For each 1𝑗𝑛, set 𝑎𝒢𝑗𝑏 if and only if 𝑎=𝑏 or there exist elements 𝑏1,,𝑏𝑗1,𝑏𝑗+1,,𝑏𝑛 and 𝑎1,,𝑎𝑗1, 𝑎𝑗+1, ,𝑎𝑛 in 𝐴 such that𝑎=𝑓𝐴𝑏1,,𝑏𝑗1,𝑏,𝑏𝑗+1,,𝑏𝑛,𝑏=𝑓𝐴𝑎1,,𝑎𝑗1,𝑎,𝑎𝑗+1,,𝑎𝑛.(2.1) Each 𝒢𝑗 for 1𝑗𝑛 is clearly a reflexive and symmetric relation on 𝐴, but as we will see is not necessarily transitive for 𝑛2. Of particular interest are the two relations 𝒢1 and 𝒢𝑛, which we will denote by and , respectively.

Example 2.1. Let 𝜏=(1) be a type with one unary operation symbol 𝑓. In this case =, and we see that for any algebra 𝒜=(𝐴;𝑓𝐴) and any elements 𝑎,𝑏𝐴, we have 𝑎𝑏 if and only if 𝑎=𝑏, or 𝑎=𝑓𝐴(𝑏) and 𝑏=𝑓𝐴(𝑎). Thus two distinct elements are related if and only if there is a cycle between them in the algebra 𝒜. The relation is transitive and hence an equivalence relation: if 𝑎𝑏 and 𝑏𝑐, and 𝑎𝑏 and 𝑏𝑐, then we have 𝑎=𝑓𝐴(𝑏), 𝑏=𝑓𝐴(𝑎), 𝑏=𝑓𝐴(𝑐), and 𝑐=𝑓𝐴(𝑏). This forces 𝑎=𝑐=𝑓𝐴(𝑏), and so 𝑎𝑐. This also tells us that each element 𝑏𝐴 can be -related to at most one element other than itself.
If the type (1) algebra 𝒜 has no cycles in it, we get simply =Δ𝐴, the diagonal relation on 𝐴. If 𝐴={𝑎,𝑏} with 𝑓𝐴(𝑎)=𝑏 and 𝑓𝐴(𝑏)=𝑎, then =𝐴×𝐴. An algebra 𝒜 in which there are some cycles but not every element that has a cycle will result in strictly between Δ𝐴 and 𝐴×𝐴.

Now consider an algebra 𝒜 of an arbitrary type 𝜏. Since there can be different operation symbols of different arities in our type, we cannot define our relations 𝒢𝑗 using the 𝑗th position as before. But we can use the first and last position entries to define left and right relations. This motivates the following definition.

Definition 2.2. Let 𝒜 be any algebra of type 𝜏. We define relations and on 𝐴 as follows. For any 𝑎,𝑏𝐴, we set
(i)𝑎𝑏 if and only if 𝑎=𝑏 or 𝑎=𝑓𝐴𝑖(𝑏,𝑏2,,𝑏𝑛𝑖) and 𝑏=𝑓𝐴𝑘(𝑎,𝑎2,,𝑎𝑛𝑘), for some 𝑖,𝑘𝐼 and some elements 𝑏2,,𝑏𝑛𝑖 and 𝑎2,,𝑎𝑛𝑘 in 𝐴.(ii)𝑎𝑏 if and only if 𝑎=𝑏 or 𝑎=𝑓𝐴𝑖(𝑏1,,𝑏𝑛𝑖1,𝑏) and 𝑏=𝑓𝐴𝑘(𝑎1,,𝑎𝑛𝑘1,𝑎), for some 𝑖,𝑘𝐼 and some elements 𝑏1,,𝑏𝑛𝑖1 and 𝑎1,,𝑎𝑛𝑘1 in 𝐴.

Again these two relations are clearly seen to be reflexive and symmetric on the base set 𝐴 of any algebra 𝒜. It is the requirement of transitivity that causes problems, and forces us to impose some restrictions on our algebra. For transitivity of on an algebra 𝒜, suppose that 𝑎, 𝑏, and 𝑐 are in 𝐴,𝑎𝑏, and 𝑏𝑐. In the special cases that 𝑎=𝑏 or 𝑏=𝑐, we certainly have 𝑎𝑐, so let us assume that 𝑎𝑏 and 𝑏𝑐. Then we have 𝑎=𝑓𝐴𝑖(𝑏,𝑏2,,𝑏𝑛𝑖) and 𝑏=𝑓𝐴𝑘(𝑎,𝑎2,,𝑎𝑛𝑘), and also 𝑏=𝑓𝐴𝑝(𝑐,𝑐2,,𝑐𝑛𝑝) and 𝑐=𝑓𝐴𝑞(𝑏,𝑑1,,𝑑𝑛𝑞), for some operation symbols 𝑓𝑖, 𝑓𝑘, 𝑓𝑝, and 𝑓𝑞 of our type and some elements 𝑏2,,𝑏𝑛𝑖, 𝑎2,,𝑎𝑛𝑘, 𝑐2,𝑐𝑛𝑝, 𝑑2,,𝑑𝑛𝑞 of set 𝐴. By substitution, we get𝑎=𝑓𝐴𝑖𝑓𝐴𝑝𝑐,𝑐2,,𝑐𝑛𝑝,𝑏2,,𝑏𝑛𝑖,𝑐=𝑓𝐴𝑞𝑓𝐴𝑘𝑎,𝑎2,,𝑎𝑛𝑘,𝑑1,,𝑑𝑛𝑞.(2.2) But we need to be able to express 𝑎 as 𝑓𝐴𝑚(𝑐,𝑒2,,𝑒𝑛𝑚) for some operation symbol 𝑓𝑚 and some elements 𝑒2,,𝑒𝑛𝑚. For type (2), this is dealt with by the requirement that 𝑓𝐴(𝑓𝐴(𝑐,𝑐2),𝑏2) can be changed to 𝑓𝐴(𝑐,𝑓𝐴(𝑐2,𝑏2)), that is, we have associativity in our algebra 𝒜. For arbitrary types, it would suffice here to have a superassociative algebra, satisfying the superassociative law:𝑓𝑖𝑓𝑗𝑥1,𝑥2,,𝑥𝑛𝑗,𝑦2,,𝑦𝑛𝑖𝑓𝑗𝑥1,𝑓𝑖𝑥2,𝑦2,,𝑦𝑛𝑖,,𝑓𝑖𝑥𝑛𝑗,𝑦2,,𝑦𝑛𝑖.(2.3) This identity would allow us to express 𝑎 as an element with 𝑐 in the left-most position and similarly to express 𝑐 in terms of 𝑎. Another way to handle this would be to define 𝑎𝑏 when 𝑎=𝑏 or 𝑎=𝑡𝐴1(𝑏,𝑏2,,𝑏𝑛) and 𝑏=𝑡𝐴2(𝑎,𝑎2,,𝑎𝑚) for some term operations 𝑡𝐴1,𝑡𝐴2 on 𝒜 and some elements 𝑎2,,𝑎𝑚,𝑏2,,𝑏𝑛 of 𝐴. In either approach, we are led to consider clones of terms.

A clone is an important kind of algebra which satisfies a superassociative law that we need here. Although clones may be defined more generally (see [2]) we define here only the term clone of type 𝜏. This term clone is a heterogeneous or multi-based algebra, having as universes or base sets the sets 𝑊𝜏(𝑋𝑛) of 𝑛-ary terms of type 𝜏, for 𝑛1. For each 𝑛1, the 𝑛 variable terms 𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛 are selected as nullary operations 𝑒𝑛1,,𝑒𝑛𝑛. And for each pair 𝑛,𝑚 of natural numbers, there is a superposition operation 𝑆𝑛𝑚, from 𝑊𝜏(𝑋𝑛)×(𝑊𝜏(𝑋𝑚))𝑛 to 𝑊𝜏(𝑋𝑚), defined by 𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑛)=𝑠(𝑡1,,𝑡𝑛).

This gives us the algebra𝑊clone𝜏=𝜏𝑋𝑛;𝑆𝑛𝑚,𝑒𝑛𝑖𝑛,𝑚1,1𝑖𝑛(2.4) called the term clone of type 𝜏. It satisfies the following three axioms called the clone axioms:

(C1)𝑆𝑝𝑚(𝑧,𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑦1,𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛),,𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑦𝑝,𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛))𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑆𝑝𝑛(𝑧,𝑦1,,𝑦𝑝),𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛), for 𝑚,𝑛,𝑝1;(C2)𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑒𝑛𝑖(𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛))𝑥𝑖, for 𝑚,𝑛1 and 1𝑖𝑛;(C3)𝑆𝑛𝑛(𝑦,𝑒𝑛1,,𝑒𝑛𝑛)𝑦, for 𝑛1.

Definition 2.3. Let 𝜏=(𝑛𝑖)𝑖𝐼be any type, and let (𝑆𝑛𝑚)𝑛,𝑚1be the superposition operations on the term clone, clone𝜏 . One defines two relations and on clone𝜏 as follows. For any terms 𝑠 and 𝑡 in clone𝜏, of arities 𝑚 and 𝑛, respectively,
(i)𝑠𝑡 if and only if 𝑠=𝑡, or 𝑠=𝑆𝑚𝑛(𝑡,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚) and 𝑡=𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑠1,,𝑠𝑛) for some terms 𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚 and 𝑠1,,𝑠𝑛 in clone𝜏;(ii)𝑠𝑡 if and only if 𝑠=𝑡, or 𝑚=𝑛 and 𝑠=𝑆𝑚𝑚(𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚,𝑡) and 𝑡=𝑆𝑚𝑚(𝑠1,,𝑠𝑚,𝑠) for some terms 𝑡1,𝑡𝑚 and 𝑠1,𝑠𝑚 in clone𝜏.

Lemma 2.4. For any type 𝜏, the relation defined on clone𝜏 is an equivalence relation on clone𝜏.

Proof. As noted above, both relations and are reflexive and symmetric by definition. Transitivity for follows from the clone axiom (C1) as above.

Transitivity of does not follow directly from the clone axioms. We will show later that this relation is transitive, once we have deduced more information about it.

A similar definition of a Green's-like relation was defined by Denecke and Jampachon in [3], but in the restricted special case of a Menger algebra of rank 𝑛. These are algebras of type (𝑛,0,,0), having one 𝑛-ary operation and 𝑛-nullary ones. Menger algebras can be formed using terms as the following: the base set 𝑊𝜏(𝑋𝑛) of all 𝑛-ary terms of type 𝜏, along with the superposition operation 𝑆𝑛𝑛 and the 𝑛-variable terms 𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛, form a Menger algebra of rank 𝑛 called the 𝑛-clone of type 𝜏. Such algebras also satisfy the clone axioms (C1), (C2), and (C3) (restricted to 𝑆𝑛𝑛). Denecke and Jampachon also defined a left Green's-like relation as well, again on the Menger algebra of rank 𝑛. Their left relation is a subset of our relation , and we will use the name in the next definition for the analogous relation in the term clone case.

Now, we extend our definition of Green's relations and on clone𝜏, to relations with respect to varieties of type 𝜏.

Definition 2.5. Let 𝑉 be any variety of type 𝜏. One defines relations 𝑉, 𝑉, and 𝑉 on clone𝜏 as follows. Let 𝑠 and 𝑡 be terms of type 𝜏, of arities 𝑚 and 𝑛, respectively. Then
(i)𝑠𝑉𝑡 if and only if 𝑠=𝑡, or𝑠𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑡,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑛Id𝑉,𝑡𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑠1,𝑠𝑚Id𝑉(2.5) for some terms 𝑡1,,𝑡𝑛 and 𝑠1,,𝑠𝑚 in clone𝜏;(ii)𝑠𝑉𝑡 if and only if 𝑛=𝑚, and 𝑠=𝑡 or𝑠𝑆𝑚𝑚𝑡1,𝑡2,,𝑡𝑚,𝑡Id𝑉,𝑡𝑆𝑚𝑚𝑠1,𝑠2,𝑠𝑚,𝑠Id𝑉(2.6) for some terms 𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚 and 𝑠1,,𝑠𝑚 in clone𝜏;(iii)𝑠𝑉𝑡 if and only if 𝑛=𝑚, and 𝑠=𝑡 or𝑠𝑆𝑚𝑚𝑡1,𝑡,,𝑡Id𝑉,𝑡𝑆𝑚𝑚𝑠1,𝑠,,𝑠Id𝑉(2.7) for some terms 𝑡1 and 𝑠1 in clone𝜏.

This definition actually includes Definition 2.3 as a special case: when 𝑉 equals the variety 𝐴𝑙𝑔(𝜏) of all algebras of type 𝜏, the relation Id𝑉 is simply equality on clone𝜏 and we obtain the relations of Definition 2.3. We remark that similar definitions could be made for 𝒜 and 𝒜 for any algebra 𝒜, using identities of 𝒜. Another possible variation is to restrict the existence of the terms 𝑡1,,𝑡𝑛 and 𝑠1,,𝑠𝑚 to terms from some subclone 𝐶 of clone𝜏; in this case we could define subrelations 𝐶𝑉 and 𝐶𝑉.

The proof of the following lemma is similar to that of Lemma 2.4.

Lemma 2.6. For any type 𝜏 and any variety 𝑉 of type 𝜏, the relation 𝑉 defined on clone𝜏 is an equivalence relation on clone𝜏.

3. The Relations 𝑉 and 𝑉

In this section, we describe some properties of the relations 𝑉, 𝑉, and 𝑉, for any variety 𝑉. We begin with the relation 𝑉.

Proposition 3.1. Let 𝑉 be any variety of type 𝜏. Then
(i)two terms of type 𝜏 of arity, at least two, are 𝑉-related if and only if they have the same arity;(ii)the relation 𝑉 is an equivalence relation on the set 𝑊𝜏(𝑋) of all terms of type 𝜏.

Proof. (i) It follows from the definition of superposition of terms that the term 𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑡1,𝑡2,,𝑡𝑚,𝑡) has the same arity as 𝑡. Thus it is built into the definition of 𝑉 that any two terms which are 𝑉-related must have the same arity. Conversely, let both 𝑠 and 𝑡 be terms of arity 𝑛2. Then we can write 𝑠=𝑆𝑛𝑛(𝑥1,𝑠,,𝑠,𝑡) and 𝑡=𝑆𝑛𝑛(𝑥1,𝑡,,𝑡,𝑠), making 𝑠𝑆𝑛𝑛(𝑥1,𝑠,,𝑠,𝑡)Id𝑉 and 𝑡𝑆𝑛𝑛(𝑥1,𝑡,,𝑡,𝑠)Id𝑉 for any variety 𝑉, and so 𝑠𝑉𝑡.
(ii) For any variety 𝑉, 𝑉 is by definition reflexive and symmetric, and we need only verify transitivity. Since only elements of the same arity can be related, we see that 𝑉 makes a partition of 𝑊𝜏(𝑋) in which all elements of 𝑊𝜏(𝑋𝑛) are related to each other for 𝑛2. This means that it suffices to verify transitivity for unary terms only. Let 𝑠, 𝑡, and 𝑢 be unary terms with 𝑠𝑉𝑡 and 𝑡𝑉𝑢. Then there exist unary terms 𝑎, 𝑏, 𝑐, and 𝑑 such that 𝑠𝑆11(𝑎,𝑡), 𝑡𝑆11(𝑏,𝑠), 𝑡𝑆11(𝑐,𝑢), and 𝑢𝑆11(𝑑,𝑡) all hold in Id𝑉. Then by substitution and the clone axiom (C1), we have 𝑠𝑆11(𝑎,𝑆11(𝑐,𝑢))𝑆11(𝑆11(𝑎,𝑐),𝑢) in Id𝑉, and similarly 𝑢𝑆11(𝑆11(𝑑,𝑏),𝑠) in Id𝑉. This makes 𝑠𝑉𝑢 as required.

We have shown that any two terms of the same arity 𝑛2 are 𝑉-related, for any variety 𝑉. Which unary terms are related, however, depends on the variety 𝑉. For instance, if the operation 𝑓𝑖 is idempotent in 𝑉, we can express the unary terms 𝑥1 and 𝑓𝑖(𝑥1,,𝑥1) in terms of each other:𝑥1𝑆11𝑥1,𝑓𝑖𝑥1,,𝑥1Id𝑉,𝑓𝑖𝑥1,,𝑥1𝑆11𝑓𝑥1,,𝑥1,𝑥1Id𝑉.(3.1) Thus 𝑥1 and 𝑓𝑖(𝑥1,,𝑥1) are 𝑉-related when 𝑓𝑖 is idempotent; but these terms need not be related if 𝑓𝑖 is not idempotent. This question will be investigated in more detail in Section 4.

Proposition 3.2. Let 𝐴𝑙𝑔(𝜏) be the class of all algebras of type 𝜏. The relation 𝐴𝑙𝑔(𝜏) is equal to the identity relation Δ𝑊𝜏(𝑋) on 𝑊𝜏(𝑋).

Proof. This was proved in [3] for the analogous relation 𝐴𝑙𝑔(𝜏) defined on the rank 𝑛 Menger algebra, the 𝑛-clone of type 𝜏. Since terms are 𝑉-related only if they have the same arity, the same proof covers the general term-clone case as well.

Example 3.3. Let 𝑉 be an idempotent variety of type 𝜏. Then it is easy to show that for any terms 𝑠 and 𝑡 of the same arity 𝑛, we have 𝑆𝑛𝑛(𝑠,𝑡,,𝑡)𝑡Id𝑉. It follows from this that 𝑠𝑆𝑛𝑛(𝑝,𝑡,,𝑡)Id𝑉 for some term 𝑝 if and only if 𝑠𝑡Id𝑉. This means that for any terms 𝑠 and 𝑡, we have 𝑠𝑉𝑡 if and only if 𝑠 and 𝑡 have the same arity and 𝑠𝑡Id𝑉. In particular, any two unary terms of type 𝜏 are 𝑉-related in this case. Combining this with Proposition 3.1 and the fact that 𝑉𝑉 shows that when 𝑉 is idempotent, two terms are 𝑉-related if and only if they have the same arity. We see also that 𝑉 is a proper subset of 𝑉 when 𝑉 is an idempotent variety.

Next we consider the right relation 𝑉. Denoting by (𝜏) the lattice of all varieties of type 𝜏, ordered by inclusion, we show first that 𝑉 is order-reversing as an operator on (𝜏).

Lemma 3.4. (i) For any varieties 𝑈,𝑊(𝜏), if 𝑈𝑊, then 𝑊𝑈.
(ii) If 𝑉 is equal to 𝑊𝜏(𝑋)2 for some variety 𝑉, then 𝑊=𝑊𝜏(𝑋)2 for all varieties 𝑊𝑉.

Proof. (i) Follows immediately from the fact that Id𝑊Id𝑈 when 𝑈𝑊, and (ii) follows immediately from (i).

Now we want to prove some facts about which pairs of terms can be 𝑉-related. Recall that 𝑋={𝑥1,𝑥2,𝑥3,} is the set of all variables used in forming terms. Our first observation is that for any two variables 𝑥𝑗 and 𝑥𝑘 of arities 𝑛 and 𝑚, respectively, we can write 𝑥𝑗=𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑥𝑘,𝑥𝑗,,𝑥𝑗). This shows that any two variables are 𝑉-related, for any variety 𝑉; we write this as 𝑋×𝑋𝑉. Next suppose that 𝑠𝑡 is an identity of 𝑉, with 𝑠 of arity 𝑛 and 𝑡 of arity 𝑚. Then 𝑠𝑆𝑚𝑛(𝑡,𝑥1,,𝑥𝑚)Id𝑉 and 𝑡𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛)Id𝑉, making 𝑠𝑉𝑡. Identifying the set Id𝑉 of all identities of 𝑉 with the subset {(𝑠,𝑡)𝑠𝑡Id𝑉} of 𝑊𝜏(𝑋)2, we see that Id𝑉𝑉.

Example 3.5. Let 𝑉 be the trivial variety TR𝜏 of type 𝜏, defined by the identity 𝑥1𝑥2. Then Id𝑉=𝑊𝜏(𝑋)2, since any identity is satisfied in 𝑉. From this and the previous comments, it follows that 𝑉 also equals 𝑊𝜏(𝑋)2 for this choice of 𝑉.

To further describe 𝑉, we need more notation. For any 𝑚1, let 𝑆𝑦𝑚𝑚 be the symmetric group of permutations of the set {1,2,,𝑚}. Let 𝑠=𝑠(𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛) be an 𝑛-ary term. For any 𝑚𝑛 and any permutation 𝜋𝑆𝑦𝑚𝑚, we will denote by 𝜋(𝑠) the 𝑚-ary term 𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑥𝜋(1),,𝑥𝜋(𝑛)). That is, 𝜋(𝑠) is the term formed from 𝑠 by relabelling the variables in 𝑠 according to the permutation 𝜋.

Proposition 3.6. let 𝑉 be any variety of type 𝜏. For any term𝑠 of type 𝜏 of arity 𝑛, and any permutation 𝜋𝑆𝑦𝑚𝑚, where 𝑚𝑛, one gets 𝑠𝑉𝜋(𝑠).

Proof. By definition 𝜋(𝑠)=𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑥𝜋(1),,𝑥𝜋(𝑛)), so that 𝜋(𝑠)𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑥𝜋(1),,𝑥𝜋(𝑛))Id𝑉. For the other direction, to express 𝑠 using 𝜋(𝑠), we use the inverse permutation 𝜋1𝑆𝑦𝑚𝑚:𝑆𝑚𝑛𝜋𝑠,𝑥𝜋1(1),,𝑥𝜋1(𝑚)=𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑥𝜋(1),,𝑥𝜋(𝑛),𝑥𝜋1(1),,𝑥𝜋1(𝑚)=𝑆𝑛𝑛𝑠,𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑥𝜋(1),𝑥𝜋1(1),,𝑥𝜋1(𝑚),,𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑥𝜋(𝑛),𝑥𝜋1(1),,𝑥𝜋1(𝑚)byC1=𝑆𝑛𝑛𝑠,𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛=𝑠.(3.2)This gives an identity in Id𝑉 and shows that 𝜋(𝑠)𝑉𝑠.

Definition 3.7. Let Σ be any set of identities. For any identity 𝑠𝑡 in Σ, with 𝑠 of arity 𝑛 and 𝑡 of arity 𝑚, let 𝜋𝑆𝑦𝑚𝑘 and 𝜌𝑆𝑦𝑚𝑟 for 𝑘𝑛 and 𝑟𝑚. Denote by 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Σ) the set of all pairs (𝜋(𝑠),𝜌(𝑡)) in 𝑊𝜏(𝑋)2 formed in this way from identities 𝑠𝑡 in Σ.

Proposition 3.8. Let 𝑉 be any variety of type 𝜏. Then (𝑋×𝑋)Id𝑉𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)𝑉.

Proof. First note that any identity 𝑥𝑗𝑥𝑘 in 𝑋×𝑋 can be produced by applying two permutations 𝜋 and 𝜌 to the identity 𝑥1𝑥1 from Id𝑉, so we have 𝑋×𝑋𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉). The existence of identity permutations also gives us Id𝑉𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉).
Now let 𝑠𝑡 be an identity of 𝑉, with 𝜋 and 𝜌 permutations on the appropriate sets. We saw above that 𝑠𝑉𝑡, and by Proposition 3.6 also 𝑠𝑉𝜋(𝑠) and 𝑡𝑉𝜌(𝑡). By the symmetry and transitivity of 𝑉 we get 𝜋(𝑠)𝑉𝜌(𝑡). This shows that 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)𝑉.

We note that as a consequence of Proposition 3.8, the equivalence relation 𝑉 is not in general an equational theory on 𝑊𝜏(𝑋). The only equational theory in which any two variables are related is Id𝑉 for 𝑉 equal to the trivial variety.

Example 3.9. In this example we consider 𝑉=𝐴𝑙𝑔(𝜏), the variety of all algebras of type 𝜏. It is well-known that for this variety 𝑉, Id𝑉=Δ𝑊𝜏(𝑋), the identity relation on 𝑊𝜏(𝑋); that is, an identity 𝑠𝑡 holds in 𝑉 if and only if 𝑠=𝑡. From Proposition, we know that 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Δ𝑊𝜏(𝑋)) is a subset of 𝑉, and we will show that we have equality in this case. Let 𝑠 and 𝑡 be terms of arities 𝑛 and 𝑚, respectively, and suppose that 𝑠𝑉𝑡. Without loss of generality, let us assume that 𝑛𝑚. Then there exist terms 𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚 and 𝑠1,,𝑠𝑛 in 𝑊𝜏(𝑋) such that𝑠𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑡,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚Id𝑉,𝑡𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑠1,𝑠𝑛Id𝑉.(3.3) The property that Id𝑉=Δ𝑊𝜏(𝑋) means that𝑠=𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑡,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚,𝑡=𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑠1,𝑠𝑛.(3.4) Then we have
𝑥𝑠=𝑠1,,𝑥𝑛=𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑡,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚=𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑠1,,𝑠𝑛,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚=𝑆𝑛𝑛𝑠,𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑠1,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚,,𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑠𝑛,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚,byC1(3.5) This equality forces a strong condition on the entries in the last line. Suppose that the variables occurring in term 𝑠 are 𝑥𝑖1,,𝑥𝑖𝑘, with 𝑘𝑛. Then we must have 𝑆𝑚𝑛(𝑠𝑖𝑗,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚)=𝑥𝑖𝑗 for each 𝑗=1,2,,𝑘. Then for each index 𝑖𝑗 there must exist an index 𝑙𝑗 such that 𝑠𝑖𝑗=𝑥𝑙𝑗 and 𝑡𝑖𝑗=𝑥𝑖𝑗. Moreover the indices 𝑙𝑗, for 1𝑗𝑘 must be distinct. This means that there is a permutation 𝜋 on the set {1,2,,𝑛}, such that 𝜋(𝑖𝑗)=𝑙𝑗, for 𝑞𝑗𝑘. Then we have𝑥𝑡=𝑡1,,𝑥𝑚=𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑠1,,𝑠𝑛=𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑠1,𝑥𝑙1,,𝑥𝑙2,,𝑥𝑙𝑘,,𝑠𝑛=𝜋(𝑠),(3.6) showing that we can obtain 𝑡 by variable permutation from 𝑠.

Example 3.10. A nontrivial variety 𝑉 of type 𝜏 is said to be normal if it does not satisfy any identity of the form 𝑥𝑗𝑡, where 𝑥𝑗 is a variable and 𝑡 is a nonvariable term. For each type 𝜏, there is a smallest normal variety 𝑁𝜏, which is defined by the set of identities {𝑠𝑡𝑠,𝑡𝑊𝜏(𝑋)𝑋}. That is, any two nonvariable terms are related by Id𝑁𝜏, while each variable is related only to itself. Using the fact that (𝑋×𝑋)Id𝑉 is always contained in 𝑉, we see that 𝑁𝜏=(𝑋×𝑋)𝑊𝜏(𝑋)2=𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑁𝜏). This gives another example of a variety 𝑉 for which 𝑉=𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉).

We can use the relation 𝑉 to characterize when a variety 𝑉 is normal.

Proposition 3.11. A variety 𝑉 of type 𝜏 is normal if and only if no variable is 𝑉-related to a nonvariable term.

Proof. When 𝑉 is a normal variety, we have 𝑁𝜏𝑉 and so by Lemma 3.4 𝑉𝑁𝜏. By the characterization of 𝑁𝜏 from Example 3.10 this means that no variable can be 𝑉-related to a nonvariable term. Conversely, suppose that 𝑉 has the property that a variable can only be related to another variable. Since Id𝑉𝑉, this means that Id𝑉 cannot contain any identity of the form 𝑥𝑗𝑡 for 𝑥𝑗 a variable and 𝑡 a nonvariable term; in other words, 𝑉 must be normal.

4. The Relation 𝑉 for Varieties of Semigroups

In this section we describe the relations 𝑉 and 𝑉 when 𝑉 is a variety of semigroups, that is, a variety of type (2) satisfying the associative identity. We denote by Sem the variety Mod{𝑥(𝑦𝑧)(𝑥𝑦)𝑧} of all semigroups. For any variety 𝑉, we use (𝑉) for the lattice of subvarieties of 𝑉; in particular (Sem) is the lattice of all semigroup varieties.

We will follow the convention for semigroup varieties of denoting the binary operation by juxtaposition, and of omitting brackets from terms. In this way, any term can be represented by a semigroup “word” consisting of a string of variable symbols as letters; for instance, the term 𝑓(𝑥1,𝑓(𝑥2,𝑓(𝑥2,𝑥1))) becomes the word 𝑥1𝑥2𝑥2𝑥1. We use this idea to define several properties of terms and identities. The length of a term is its length as a word, the total number of occurrences of variables in the term. An identity 𝑠𝑡 is called regular if the two terms 𝑠 and 𝑡 contain exactly the same variable symbols. A set of identities is said to be regular if all the identities in the set are regular, and a variety 𝑉 is called regular if the set Id𝑉 of all its identities is regular. A semigroup identity 𝑠𝑡 is called periodic if 𝑠=𝑥𝑎 and 𝑡=𝑥𝑏 for some variable 𝑥 and some natural numbers 𝑎𝑏. A variety of semigroups is called uniformly periodic if it satisfies a periodic identity. A variety is not uniformly periodic if and only if all its identities 𝑠𝑡 have the property that 𝑠 and 𝑡 have equal lengths. For more information on uniformly periodic varieties, see [4].

Let 𝑠=𝑠(𝑥1,,𝑥𝑛) be a term of some arity 𝑛1, and let 𝜋 be a permutation from 𝑆𝑦𝑚𝑚 for some 𝑚𝑛. In Section 3 we defined 𝜋(𝑠) to be the term 𝑠(𝑥𝜋(𝑥1),,𝑥𝜋(𝑥𝑛)) formed from 𝑠 by permutation of the variables in 𝑠 according to 𝜋. An important feature of this process is that the term 𝜋(𝑠) has the same structure as the term 𝑠, in the sense that the semantic tree of the term 𝜋(𝑠) is isomorphic as a graph to the semantic tree for 𝑠. In particular, the term 𝜋(𝑠) has the same length and the same number of distinct variables occurring in it as 𝑠 does. Which variables occur need not be the same; for instance, 𝑠=𝑥1𝑥2 can be permuted into 𝜋(𝑠)=𝑥3𝑥4, changing the arity of the term and which variables occur. As a result, a regular identity such as 𝑥1𝑥2𝑥2𝑥1 can be permuted by two different permutations 𝜋 and 𝜌 into a nonregular identity such as 𝑥3𝑥4𝑥5𝑥6. Thus the set 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉) from Section 3 need not be regular even when Id𝑉 is regular. This motivates a new definition. We will call an identity 𝑠𝑡 permutation-regular if the number of distinct variables occurring in 𝑠 and 𝑡 is the same. As usual, a set of identities will be called permutation-regular if all the identities in the set are permutation-regular. We will make use of the following basic fact.

Lemma 4.1. Let 𝑉 be a variety of semigroups. If 𝑉 is regular, then 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)is permutation-regular.

We saw in Section 3 that any two terms of the same arity 𝑛2 are 𝑉-related, for any variety 𝑉, and that only terms of the same arity can be 𝑉-related. Thus the only thing of interest for 𝑉 when 𝑉 is a variety of semigroups is which unary terms are related to each other. Let 𝑇1 denote the set of unary semigroup terms, so that 𝑇1={𝑥𝑖|𝑖1}.

Proposition 4.2. For any variety 𝑉 of semigroups, 𝑉𝑇21=𝑉𝑇21. That is, two unary terms are 𝑉-related if and only if they are 𝑉-related.

Proof. Let 𝑥𝑖 and 𝑥𝑗 be two unary terms, for 𝑖,𝑗1, with 𝑖𝑗. Then 𝑥𝑖𝑉𝑥𝑗 if and only if 𝑥𝑖𝑆11(𝑥𝑗,𝑥𝑝) and 𝑥𝑗𝑆11(𝑥𝑖,𝑥𝑞) both hold in Id𝑉, for some unary terms 𝑥𝑝 and 𝑥𝑞. These identities hold if and only if 𝑥𝑖𝑥𝑗𝑝 and 𝑥𝑗𝑥𝑖𝑞 hold in 𝑉. Similarly, 𝑥𝑖𝑉𝑥𝑗 if and only if 𝑥𝑖𝑆11(𝑥𝑝,𝑥𝑗) and 𝑥𝑗𝑆11(𝑥𝑞,𝑥𝑖) both hold in Id𝑉, for some unary terms 𝑥𝑝 and 𝑥𝑞, which is also equivalent to having both 𝑥𝑖𝑥𝑗𝑝 and 𝑥𝑗𝑥𝑖𝑞 in Id𝑉.

This result allows us to completely characterize the relation 𝑉 for 𝑉 a variety of semigroups, and begins our description of 𝑉. Moreover, we have proved the following useful characterization of when two unary terms are 𝑉-related.

Corollary 4.3. Let 𝑉 be a variety of semigroups and let 𝑥𝑖 and 𝑥𝑗 be unary terms with 𝑖𝑗. Then 𝑥𝑖𝑉𝑥𝑗 if and only if the identities 𝑥𝑖𝑥𝑝𝑗 and 𝑥𝑗𝑥𝑞𝑖 hold in 𝑉 for some natural numbers 𝑝, 𝑞1.

Now we describe how the relations 𝑉 behave, starting with unary terms.

Proposition 4.4. Let 𝑉 be a variety of semigroups which is not uniformly periodic. Then 𝑉𝑇21=𝑉𝑇21=Δ𝑇1; that is, two unary terms are related by 𝑉 if and only if they are equal.

Proof. Let 𝑥𝑖 and 𝑥𝑗 be two unary terms which are 𝑉- or 𝑉-related. By Corollary 4.3, this forces identities of the form 𝑥𝑖𝑥𝑝𝑗 and 𝑥𝑗𝑥𝑞𝑖 to hold in 𝑉, for some natural numbers 𝑝 and 𝑞. But when 𝑉 is not uniformly periodic, an identity of the form 𝑥𝑎𝑥𝑏 can hold in 𝑉 if and only if 𝑎=𝑏. Thus we must have 𝑖=𝑝𝑗 and 𝑗=𝑞𝑖. This can only happen if 𝑖=𝑗, and the terms 𝑥𝑖 and 𝑥𝑗 are in fact equal.

What happens with unary terms for uniformly periodic varieties depends on the particular variety. We recall from Section 3 that 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)𝑉. We will show that if 𝑉 is both regular and uniformly periodic, then Id𝑉𝑇21=𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)𝑇21, but 𝑉𝑇21 can be larger.

Lemma 4.5. If 𝑉 is a variety of semigroups which is both regular and uniformly periodic, then Id𝑉𝑇21=𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)𝑇21.

Proof. Since Id𝑉𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉) by definition, we know that Id𝑉𝑇21𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)𝑇21. For the opposite inclusion, suppose that 𝑥𝑖𝑥𝑗 is in 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉) for some unary terms 𝑥𝑖 and 𝑥𝑗. Then there exist some identity 𝑠𝑡 in Id𝑉 and some permutations 𝜋 and 𝜌 such that 𝑥𝑖=𝜋(𝑠) and 𝑥𝑗=𝜌(𝑡). Since permutations do not change the number of variables occurring or the length of a term, both 𝑠 and 𝑡 must look like 𝑥𝑖𝑘 and 𝑥𝑗𝑚, respectively, for some variables 𝑥𝑘 and 𝑥𝑚. Since 𝑉 is regular and 𝑠𝑡 is in Id𝑉, the variables 𝑥𝑘 and 𝑥𝑚 must in fact be the same. Therefore 𝑥𝑖𝑥𝑗 is actually in Id𝑉.

Any uniformly periodic variety 𝑉 must satisfy an identity of the form 𝑥𝑎𝑥𝑎+𝑏 for some natural numbers 𝑎 and 𝑏. We denote by 𝐵𝑎,𝑏 the variety Mod{𝑥(𝑦𝑧)(𝑥𝑦)𝑧,𝑥𝑎𝑥𝑎+𝑏}, known as a Burnside variety. Thus any uniformly periodic variety of semigroups is a subvariety of 𝐵𝑎,𝑏 for some 𝑎,𝑏1. An important fact about the identities of the variety 𝐵𝑎,𝑏 is the following: an identity of the form 𝑥𝑢𝑥𝑣 holds in this variety if and only if either 𝑢=𝑣 or both 𝑢,𝑣𝑎 and 𝑢𝑣 modulo 𝑏. Combining this fact with Corollary 4.3 allows us to describe which unary terms are 𝑉-related for the variety 𝑉=𝐵𝑎,𝑏.

Corollary 4.6. Let 𝑉=𝐵𝑎,𝑏, for 𝑎,𝑏1. Then 𝑥𝑖𝑉𝑥𝑗 if and only if both 𝑖,𝑗𝑎 and the congruences 𝑖𝑝𝑗 modulo 𝑏 and 𝑗𝑞𝑖 modulo 𝑏 have solutions 𝑝,𝑞1.

Some basic number theory now provides us with some examples. Let us note that in 𝑉=𝐵𝑎,𝑏, the unary terms are (up to equivalence modulo Id𝑉 and hence equivalence in 𝑉 as well) 𝑥,𝑥2,,𝑥𝑎+𝑏1. In the case 𝑎=𝑏=1, we have all unary terms equivalent, and 𝑉𝑇21=𝑇21. For 𝑉=𝐵𝑎,1 or 𝑉=𝐵𝑎,2, for any 𝑎1, it is easy to see that 𝑉𝑇21 is just Id𝑉𝑇21. But for 𝑉=𝐵1,𝑎 when 𝑎 is a prime number, the terms 𝑥,𝑥2,,𝑥𝑎1 are all 𝑉-related to each other, but not to 𝑥𝑎; in this case more terms are related by 𝑉 than those related by Id𝑉. For 𝑉=𝐵2.5, we can show that there are 3 distinct classes of terms under 𝑉: {𝑥}, {𝑥2,𝑥3,𝑥4,𝑥6} and {𝑥5}. This shows that for this choice of 𝑉, we have 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)𝑉𝑊𝜏(𝑋).

Finally, we consider the relation 𝑉 for terms of arbitrary arity. Here too, uniformly periodic varieties behave differently from those which are not uniformly periodic.

Proposition 4.7. If 𝑉 is a variety of semigroups which is not uniformly periodic, then 𝑉=𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉).

Proof. This proof is a modification of the argument from Example 3.9. First, by Proposition 3.8 we have 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉)𝑉, so we need to show the opposite inclusion. Let 𝑠 and 𝑡 be terms of arities 𝑛 and 𝑚, respectively, with 𝑛𝑚, and suppose that 𝑠𝑉𝑡. Then there exist terms 𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚 and 𝑠1,,𝑠𝑛 in 𝑊𝜏(𝑋) such that𝑠𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑡,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚Id𝑉,𝑡𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑠1,𝑠𝑛Id𝑉.(4.1) Then we have𝑠𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑡,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑠1,,𝑠𝑛,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚𝑆𝑛𝑛𝑠,𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑠1,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚,,𝑆𝑚𝑛𝑠𝑛,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚,byC1(4.2) Where in Example 3.9 we have equality of terms, we now have only equivalence modulo Id𝑉. However, the condition that 𝑉 is not uniformly periodic means that the term 𝑆𝑛𝑛(𝑠,𝑆𝑚𝑛(𝑠1,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚),,𝑆𝑚𝑛(𝑠𝑛,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚)) must have the same length as 𝑠. This is sufficient to force the same requirement for variable entries as before to produce our permutation 𝜋. Let the variables occurring in term 𝑠 be 𝑥𝑖1,,𝑥𝑖𝑘, with 𝑘𝑛. Then we must have 𝑆𝑚𝑛(𝑠𝑖𝑗,𝑡1,,𝑡𝑚)=𝑥𝑖𝑗 for each 𝑗=1,2,,𝑘. Then for each index 𝑖𝑗 there must exist an index 𝑙𝑗 such that 𝑠𝑖𝑗=𝑥𝑙𝑗 and 𝑡𝑖𝑗=𝑥𝑖𝑗. Moreover the indices 𝑙𝑗, for 1𝑗𝑘 must be distinct. This means that there is a permutation 𝜋 on the set {1,2,,𝑛}, such that 𝜋(𝑖𝑗)=𝑙𝑗, for 𝑞𝑗𝑘. Then we have𝑥𝑡=𝑡1,,𝑥𝑚=𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑠1,,𝑠𝑛=𝑆𝑛𝑚𝑠,𝑠1,𝑥𝑙1,,𝑥𝑙2,,𝑥𝑙𝑘,,𝑠𝑛=𝜋(𝑠).(4.3)This shows that 𝑡=𝜋(𝑠) for some permutation 𝜋, and hence that 𝑉𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉).

The converse of this proposition is not however true. As an example we consider the smallest normal variety of type (2), the variety 𝑍𝑒𝑟𝑜 of zero semigroups defined by 𝑥𝑦𝑧𝑤. This is a uniformly periodic but not regular variety, but the relation 𝑉 for this variety 𝑉 is equal to 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉), from Example 3.10.

At the other extreme is the variety 𝐵1,1 of idempotent semigroups or bands. The lattice (𝐵1,1) of band varieties is known to be countably infinite and its structure has been completely described by Birjukov [5], Fennemore [6, 7], Gerhard [8], and Gerhard and Petrich [9]. Our next result shows that varieties of bands are the only semigroup varieties for which 𝑉 is the total relation 𝑊𝜏(𝑋) on 𝑊𝜏(𝑋).

Theorem 4.8. Let 𝑉 be a variety of semigroups. Then 𝑉=𝑊𝜏(𝑋) if and only if 𝑉 is a subvariety of the variety 𝐵1,1 of bands.

Proof. First let 𝑉 be a variety of bands, so 𝑉𝐵1,1. Then it is easy to show by induction on the complexity of terms that for any two terms 𝑠 and 𝑡, of any arities 𝑛 and 𝑚, respectively, we have 𝑠(𝑡,𝑡,,𝑡)𝑡Id𝑉. This means that we can always write 𝑡𝑆𝑛𝑚(𝑠,𝑡,,𝑡)Id𝑉 and 𝑠𝑆𝑚𝑛(𝑡,𝑠,,𝑠)Id𝑉, making 𝑠𝑉𝑡.
Conversely, suppose that 𝑉 has the property that any two terms (of any arities) are related by 𝑉. Then the term 𝑥 is related to the term 𝑥2, so we must be able to express 𝑥𝑆11(𝑥2,𝑝)Id𝑉 for some unary term 𝑝=𝑥𝑐, for some 𝑐1. In particular, our variety 𝑉 must satisfy an identity of the form 𝑥𝑥𝑎 for some 𝑎1. If 𝑎=1, we have 𝑥𝑥2Id𝑉, and we have shown that 𝑉 is a variety of bands. If 𝑎>1, then we can deduce the following identities from 𝑥𝑥𝑎 :𝑥𝑥𝑎𝑥2𝑎1𝑥3𝑎2𝑥Id𝑉2𝑥𝑎+1𝑥2𝑎𝑥3𝑎1𝑥Id𝑉3𝑥𝑎+2𝑥2𝑎+1𝑥3𝑎𝑥Id𝑉𝑎1𝑥2(𝑎1)𝑥3(𝑎1)𝑥4(𝑎1)Id𝑉.(4.4) Now we also know that 𝑥 is 𝑉-related to 𝑥𝑎1, which means that we can write 𝑥𝑆11(𝑥𝑎1,𝑞)Id𝑉 for some unary term 𝑞=𝑥𝑘, for some 𝑘. Therefore, we get 𝑥𝑥𝑘(𝑎1)Id𝑉. A similar argument applied to 𝑥2𝑉𝑥𝑎1 then gives 𝑥2𝑥𝑚(𝑎1)Id𝑉 for some 𝑚. Since 𝑥𝑘(𝑎1)𝑥𝑚(𝑘1) is in Id𝑉 from above, we see that by transitivity we have 𝑥𝑥2 in Id𝑉, and 𝑉 is a variety of bands.

Theorem 4.9. Let 𝑉=𝐵𝑎,𝑏 for some 𝑎,𝑏1. Let 𝑡 be any term of arity 𝑛2 which has at least one variable 𝑥𝑘 occurring in it a number of times which is congruent to 1 modulo 𝑏. Then 𝑥𝑎𝑉𝑡𝑎.

Proof. We can always write 𝑡𝑎=𝑆1𝑛(𝑎𝑎,𝑝) for some 𝑛-ary term 𝑝, by taking 𝑝=𝑡. But we also need to be able to write 𝑥𝑎𝑆𝑛1(𝑡𝑎,𝑞1,,𝑞𝑛)Id𝑉 for some unary terms 𝑞1,,𝑞𝑛. Let 𝑥𝑘 be a variable which occurs in 𝑡 exactly 𝑣 times, where 𝑣 is congruent to 1 modulo 𝑏. For the term 𝑞𝑘, we use 𝑥, and for all the other terms 𝑞1,,𝑞𝑛, we use 𝑥𝑏. Then 𝑆𝑛1(𝑡𝑎,𝑞1,,𝑞𝑛)=𝑡𝑎(𝑥𝑏,,𝑥𝑏,𝑥,𝑥𝑏,,𝑥𝑏)=(𝑥𝑞𝑏+1)𝑎 for some natural number 𝑞. Then in 𝐵𝑎,𝑏 we have (𝑥𝑞𝑏+1)𝑎𝑥𝑎𝑞𝑏+𝑎𝑥𝑎, as required.

Corollary 4.10. Let 𝑉=𝐵𝑎,𝑏 for some 𝑎,𝑏1 with 𝑎+𝑏3. Then 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉) is a proper subset of 𝑉, which is a proper subset of 𝑊𝜏(𝑋)on𝑊𝜏(𝑋).

Proof. By the previous theorem, we have 𝑥𝑎𝑉(𝑥𝑦)𝑎. Since the terms 𝑥𝑎 and (𝑥𝑦)𝑎 contain different numbers of variables, and 𝑉 is regular, the identity 𝑥𝑎(𝑥𝑦)𝑎 cannot be in 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉). Thus 𝑃𝑒𝑟𝑚(Id𝑉) is a proper subset of 𝑉. The remaining claim follows from Theorem 4.8.

Acknowledgment

This research is supported by the NSERC of Canada.