Abstract

We establish, by means of a large class of continuous t-representable intuitionistic fuzzy t-conorms, a factorization of an intuitionistic fuzzy relation (IFR) into a unique indifference component and a family of regular strict components. This result generalizes a previous factorization obtained by Dimitrov (2002) with the intuitionistic fuzzy t-conorm. We provide, for a continuous t-representable intuitionistic fuzzy t-norm , a characterization of the -transitivity of an IFR. This enables us to determine necessary and sufficient conditions on a -transitive IFR under which a strict component of satisfies pos-transitivity and negative transitivity.

1. Introduction

In the real life, individual or collective preferences are not always crisp; they can be also ambiguous. Since 1965 when Zadeh [1] introduced fuzzy set theory, researchers [2โ€“11] modelled such preferences by (binary) fuzzy relation (simply denoted by FR) on that is, a function where is a set of alternatives with In this case, for is interpreted as the degree to which is โ€œat least as good as" If then is crisp, and we denote by and by Literature on the theory of fuzzy relations and on applications of fuzzy relations in other fields such as economics and in particular social choice theory is growing.

Since 1983 when Atanassov [12, 13] introduced intuitionistic fuzzy sets (IFSs), some scholars [14โ€“19] modelled ambiguous preferences by a (binary) intuitionistic fuzzy relation (IFR) on , that is, a function where In this case, is the degree to which is โ€œat least as good as" , and is the degree to which is not โ€œat least as good as" The positive real number (since usually called fuzzy index, indicates the degree of incomparability between and . In this paper, we simply write . Clearly, we have two particular cases: (i) if that is, then becomes an FR on , and (ii) if and , then becomes the well-known (binary) crisp relation. In the first case, we simply write and in the second case, we have (i.e., ).

A factorization of a binary relation is an important question in preference modelling. In that view, Dimitrov [18] established a factorization of an IFR into an indifference and a strict component in the particular case where the union is defined by means of the () -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -conorm. Recently, Cornelis et al. [20] established some results on -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -norms (i.e., where is a fuzzy -conorm, and is a fuzzy -norm satisfying on -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -conorms (i.e., ) and on intuitionistic fuzzy implications. Thereby, our goal is to generalize Dimitrov's framework [18] and to establish some results on IFRs by means of continuous -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -norms and -conorms.

The aim of this paper is (i) to study the standard completeness of an IFR, (ii) to establish a characterization of the -transitivity of an IFR, (iii) to generalize the factorization of an IFR established by Dimitrov [18], and (iv) to determine necessary and sufficient conditions on a -transitive IFR under which a given strict component of (obtained in our factorization) satisfies respectively pos-transitivity and negative transitivity.

First we establish some useful results on -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -norms, -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -conorms, and intuitionistic fuzzy implications.

The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we recall some basic notions and properties on fuzzy operators and intuitionistic fuzzy operators which we need throughout the paper. We also establish some useful results on fuzzy implications and intuitionistic fuzzy implications. Section 3 has three subsections. In Section 3.1, we recall some basic and useful definitions on IFRs. In Section 3.2, we introduce the standard completeness, namely, a -completeness of an IFR. We make clear that the notion of completeness introduced by Dimitrov [18] is not standard, but it is weaker than a standard one. In Section 3.3, we establish, for a given a characterization of the -transitivity of an IFR. Section 4 is devoted to a new factorization of an IFR, and it has two subsections. In Section 4.1, we recall the factorization of an IFR established by Dimitrov [18] with the intuitionistic fuzzy -conorm. We point out some intuitive difficulties of the strict component obtained in [18]. In Section 4.2, we introduce definitions of an indifference and a strict component of an IFR, and we establish a general factorization of an IFR for a large class of continuous -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -conorms. Section 5 contains two subsections. In Section 5.1, we introduce intuitionistic fuzzy counterparts of pos-transitivity and negative transitivity of a crisp relation. We justify that there exists some IFRs (noncrisp and non FRs) which violate each of these two properties. This forces us in Section 5.2 to establish necessary and sufficient conditions on a -transitive IFR such that a strict component of satisfies, respectively, pos-transitivity and negative transitivity. Section 6 contains some concluding remarks. The proofs of our results are in the Appendix. (This was suggested by an anonymous referee.)

2. Preliminaries on Operators

Let be an order in defined by and . is a complete lattice. and are the units of

In the following section, we recall some definitions, examples, and well-known results on fuzzy -norms, fuzzy -conorms, fuzzy implications, and fuzzy coimplicators.

2.1. Review on Fuzzy Operators

We firstly recall notions on fuzzy -norms and fuzzy -conorms (see [21, 22]).

A fuzzy -norm (resp. a fuzzy -conorm) is an increasing, commutative, and associative binary operation on with a neutral 1 (resp. 0). The dual of a fuzzy -norm is a fuzzy -conorm that is, , .

Let us recall two usual families of fuzzy -norms and fuzzy -conorms. The Frank -norms that is, , where , and are the minimum fuzzy -norm, the product fuzzy -norm, and the ukasiewicz fuzzy -norm, respectively. The Frank -conorms that is, , where , and are the maximum fuzzy -conorm, the product fuzzy -conorm, and the ukasiewicz fuzzy -conorm, respectively.

A fuzzy -norm (fuzzy -conorm ) is strict if , implies (resp. , , implies ). The product fuzzy -norm (resp. the product fuzzy -conorm) is an example of a strict fuzzy -norm (resp. fuzzy -conorm).

We have the following properties:

Throughout the paper, is a continuous fuzzy -norm, and is a continuous fuzzy -conorm.

In the following, we recall some definitions and examples on fuzzy implications and fuzzy coimplicators based on fuzzy -norms and fuzzy -conorms, respectively (see [21โ€“23]).

The fuzzy -implication associated to is a binary operation on defined by The fuzzy coimplicator associated to is a binary operation on defined by

Let us recall some usual examples of these fuzzy operators.

The fuzzy -implication associated to is defined by The fuzzy coimplicator associated to is defined by The fuzzy -implication associated to is defined by The fuzzy coimplicator associated to is defined by The fuzzy -implication associated to is defined by The fuzzy coimplicator associated to is defined by

We complete the previous examples by giving expressions of fuzzy R-implications of the other Frank fuzzy -norms and fuzzy coimplicators of the other Frank fuzzy -conorms:

We recall some useful properties on fuzzy implications and fuzzy coimplicators.

Proposition 2.1 (See [4, 5, 9, 21, 23]). For all ,
(1), and ;(2), and ;(3)(4)(5)

In the following, we recall some useful definitions and results on intuitionistic fuzzy operators.

2.2. Review on Intuitionistic Fuzzy Operators

Definition 2.2 (See [20]). An intuitionistic fuzzy -norm is an increasing, commutative, and associative binary operation on satisfying
() An intuitionistic fuzzy -conorm is an increasing, commutative, associative binary operation on satisfying

Cornelis et al. [20] introduced an important class of intuitionistic fuzzy -norms (resp. -conorms) based on fuzzy -norms (resp. fuzzy -conorms).

Definition 2.3. An intuitionistic fuzzy -norm (resp. -conorm ) is called -representable if there exists a fuzzy -norm and a fuzzy -conorm (resp. a fuzzy -conorm and fuzzy -norm ) such that (resp. .
and (resp. and ) are called the representants of (resp.

The theorem below states conditions under which a pair of connectives on gives rise to a -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -norm (-conorm).

Theorem 2.4 (see Cornelis et al. [20, Theorem , pages 60โ€“61]). Given a fuzzy -norm and a fuzzy -conorm satisfying
The mappings and defined by, for and in and , are, respectively, a -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -norm and -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -conorm.

Throughout the paper, we consider only continuous -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -conorms (shortly if--conorm) and continuous -representable intuitionistic fuzzy -norms (shortly if--norm). They are denoted by and , respectively, where

From the previous result, we deduce some examples of if--norms and if--conorms.

Example 2.5. and are, respectively, if--norm and if--conorm associated to and since
and are, respectively, if--norm and if--conorm associated to and since and are, respectively, if--norm and if--conorm associated to and since

Definition 2.6 (see Cornelis et al. [20, Definition , page 64]). The intuitionistic fuzzy R-implication (shortly if-R-implication) associated with an if--norm is a binary operation on defined by: , .
The intuitionistic fuzzy coimplicator (shortly if-coimplicator) associated with an if--conorm is a binary operation on defined by: , .

We establish in the sequel some new and basic results on the previous implications. These results will be useful later.

2.3. Some Basic Results on Fuzzy Implications and If-Implications

The following result establishes two links between the fuzzy R-implication and the fuzzy coimplicator

Proposition 2.7. Let and such that Then
for all if and are dual, then

The following result gives expressions of an if-R-implication and an if-coimplicator by means of and

Lemma 2.8. For all ,(1);(2).

We now introduce a new condition which can be satisfied by a if--conorm

Definition 2.9. satisfies condition if

Let us end this section by giving some examples of if--conorms satisfying condition This justifies that the class of continuous -representable if--conorms satisfying condition is not empty.

Proposition 2.10. For all satisfies condition If and are dual, then the restriction of on satisfies condition

In the next section, we recall some basic notions on IFRs and study its standard completeness (see Atanassov [12], Bustince and Burillo [15], and Dimitrov [17, 18]). We establish, for a given a characterization of the -transitivity of an IFR

3. Preliminaries on IFRs

3.1. Review on IFRs

An IFS in is an expression given by , where and are functions satisfying the condition The numbers and denote, respectively, the degree of membership and the degree of nonmembership of the element in The number is an index of the element in Obviously, when that is, the IFS is a fuzzy set (simply denoted by FS) in . In this case,

Let and be two IFSs, and let . The intuitionistic fuzzy union associated to is an IFS defined by (we recall that if and are FSs, and and are dual, then becomes the well-known fuzzy union defined by ). And if and are crisp, becomes the crisp union). As defined in the Introduction, an IFR in is an IFS in .

We complete some basic definitions on IFRs.

Definition 3.1. Let be an IFR.
is reflexive if . is symmetric if and . is -symmetric if , is perfect antisymmetric if The converse of is the IFR denoted and defined by , and .

In the following, we recall the well-known notion of completeness of a crisp relation in We then present definition of the standard completeness of a FR and its two usual and particular cases (weak completeness and strong completeness). Following that line, we introduce the definition of the standard completeness of an IFR. We establish a link between that standard definition and the one introduced by Dimitrov (see [17, 18]). And we write the two particular cases of that standard definition.

3.2. Intuitionistic Fuzzy Standard Completeness (-Completeness)

Let be a reflexive IFR and .

When is a crisp relation, is complete if that is,

When is a FR, for the fuzzy -conorm is -complete if that is, In particular, if , we simply say that is strongly complete, that is, If , we simply say that is weakly complete, that is, (see Fono and Andjiga [7, Definition , page 375]).

In the general case where is an IFR and , we have the following generic version of the standard completeness of

Definition 3.2. is -complete if that is,

Remark 3.3. If an IFR becomes a FR, and and are dual, then -completeness becomes -completeness. Furthermore, if becomes crisp, then -completeness and -completeness become crisp completeness.

Dimitrov (see [17, Definition , page 151]) introduced the following version of completeness of an IFR: is -complete if ,

It is important to notice that -completeness is not a version of the standard completeness. However, the following result shows that it is weaker than each version of the standard completeness.

Proposition 3.4. If is -complete, then is -complete.

As for FRs, we deduce the two following interesting particular cases of -completeness when .

Example 3.5. Let be a reflexive IFR and .
(1)If , then is -complete if , In this case, we simply say that is strongly complete.(2)If , then is -complete if , In this case, we simply say that is weakly complete.

We notice that, if becomes a FR, then intuitionistic strong completeness of and the intuitionistic weak completeness of become, respectively, fuzzy strong completeness of and fuzzy weak completeness of Furthermore, as for FRs, intuitionistic strong completeness implies intuitionistic weak completeness.

Throughout the paper, is a reflexive, weakly complete, and -symmetric IFR.

In the sequel, we define -transitivity of an IFR We introduce and analyze four elements of They enable us to obtain a characterization of the -transitivity of which generalizes the one obtained earlier by Fono and Andjiga [7] for FRs.

3.3. -transitivity of an IFR: Definition and Characterization

Let and be the if-R-implication associated to

Definition 3.6. is -transitive if ,

If becomes a FR and and are dual, then the -transitivity becomes the usual -transitivity, that is, If becomes a crisp relation, then the -transitivity and the -transitivity become the crisp transitivity, that is,

We write the particular case of the -transitivity where

Example 3.7. If then R is -transitive if , We simply say that is transitive.

To establish a characterization of the -transitivity of , we need the following four elements of associated to

Let us introduce and analyze these elements of .

Definition 3.8. For all ,
(1)(2)(3) = [, [(), , (4) = , [(), , .

The next result shows that are elements of and deduces expressions of and

Proposition 3.9. (1)For all .(2)(i) is the minimum of and (ii)(iii) is the minimum of and (iv)

The following remark gives some comparisons of those elements of .

Remark 3.10. For all ,(1)(2)

The following result shows that in the particular case where is strongly complete, the four reals and become simple.

Corollary 3.11. Let be an IFR, and let
(1)If is strongly complete and then (2)If is strongly complete and then

In the particular case where and are dual and becomes a FR, we have some links between and for Furthermore, we obtain expressions of introduced earlier by Fono and Andjiga (see [7, page 375]).

Corollary 3.12. If and are dual and is a FR, then
(1)(2)

We end this section by establishing by means of those four elements of a characterization of the -transitivity of an IFR . Before that, let us recall a characterization of the -transitivity of a FR: if and are dual, and the IFR becomes a FR, then Fono and Andjiga (see [7, Lemma , page 375]) used the four reals , and defined in Corollary 3.12, to obtain the following characterization of the -transitivity of

R is -transitive on if and only if

We generalize that result for an IFR. Therefore, we obtain our first key result.

Lemma 3.13. Let
The two following statements are equivalent:
(i) is -transitive on ;(ii)

In the following section, we study a factorization of For that, we proceed as follows: (i) we recall the factorization of an IFR established by Dimitrov [18]; (ii) we notice some similarities between that factorization and those established earlier on FRs by Dutta [3], Richardson [10], and Fono and Andjiga [7]; (iii) using the vocabulary used by these authors for the factorization of FRs, we write Dimitrov's [18] factorization in a simple and elegant way for the if--conorm (see Lemma 4.2); (iv) we point out some intuitive difficulties of the strict component obtained in [18]; (v) we introduce definitions of an indifference and a strict component of an IFR, and we complete Lemma 4.2 to obtain a general factorization of an IFR when the union is defined by means of a given continuous -representable if--conorm satisfying condition

4. Factorization of an IFR

4.1. Review on Dimitrov's Results and Some Comments

Dimitrov proposed a factorization of an IFR and obtained the following result.

Proposition 4.1 (see Dimitrov [18, Proposition ], or Dimitrov [17, Proposition , page 152]). Let be the if-t-conorm, and let be an IFR which is reflexive, -complete and -symmetric; and are two IFRs such that
(i),(ii) is symmetric,(iii) is perfect antisymmetric,(iv)
Then, for all ,
(1) where (2) where

After a careful check, we notice that, in the particular case where becomes a FR, conditions (4.1) and (4.3) become some known notions introduced earlier by Dutta [3] and, used by Richardson [10] and, Fono and Andjiga [7].

Let be an IFR.

(1)If becomes a FR, the strict component of becomes the fuzzy strict component of and thus, condition (4.1) of the previous result becomes condition โ€œ is simple," that is, For convenience and as in fuzzy case, we also call condition (4.1): โ€œ is simple."(2)The strict component of obtained in the previous result satisfies the following condition:

If becomes a FR, condition (4.5) becomes the condition โ€œ is regular," that is, , For convenience and as in fuzzy case, we also call condition (4.5): โ€œ is regular."

With these remarks on the intuitionistic fuzzy strict component obtained in Dimitrov [18], we rewrite Proposition 4.1 as follows:

โ€œ is regular and is defined by (4.2) if is perfect antisymmetric and simple, is symmetric, and for โ€

An interesting question is to check if this version of Dimitrov's result remains true for

The following result shows that this is true. More precisely, it establishes a generalization of the previous version of Dimitrov's result. And we obtain our second key result.

Lemma 4.2. Let be a reflexive, weakly complete and -symmetric IFR; and are two IFRs such that: (i) , (ii) is symmetric, (iii) is perfect antisymmetric, (iv) is simple. Then,
(1) is defined by (4.2);(2) is regular.

Otherwise, let us also point out some intuitive difficulties of the strict component obtained by Dimitrov in the factorization of Proposition 4.1.

(1)The component defined by (4.3) is obtained for the particular t-representable if-t-conorm .(2)The discontinuity of that is,(i)for all , the degree is insensitive for the variability of and . For illustration, if or then But if then (ii)for all , the degree is insensitive for the variability of and . For illustration, if or , then But if then

The previous observations force us to complete and generalize the factorization of Dimitrov for a if-t-conorm satisfying condition .

4.2. A New and General Factorization of an IFR

First at all, we introduce formally a definition of โ€œindifference of an IFR" and โ€œstrict component of an IFR."

Definition 4.3. Let satisfying condition be an IFR; and are two IFRs. and are โ€œindifference of " and โ€œstrict component of " associated to , respectively, if the following conditions are satisfied:

With the results of Lemma 4.2, the equality of (4.7) becomes the following equation: which is equivalent to the following system:

To establish a new and general factorization, we need the following lemma which is our third key result.

Lemma 4.4. Let be an IFR, and let such that Then,
(i)(4.9)() and (4.9)() have at least one solution;(ii)each solution of (4.9)() is strictly positive, and each solution of (4.9)() is strictly least than 1;(iii)if satisfies condition then (4.8) or (4.9) has at least one solution;(iv)if satisfies condition then the element is the optimal solution of (4.8) or (4.9), that is, is the upper solution of (4.9), and is the lowest solution of (4.9)(v)furthermore, if or is a strict if-t-conorm (i.e., and are strict) satisfying condition then is the unique solution of (4.8) or (4.9).

We now establish the result of factorization which is the first main result of our paper.

Theorem 4.5. Let satisfying condition be an IFR; and are two IFRs.
The two following statements are equivalent:
(1) and are โ€œindifference" and โ€œstrict component of " associated to , respectively;(2)(i)(ii) (4.9), (4.9), and

The previous factorization gives a unique indifference of However, as in fuzzy case and contrary to the crisp case, for an IFR and for satisfying the previous result generates a family of strict components of More interesting is that family has an optimal element called the optimal strict component of associated to

Let us give expressions of optimal intuitionistic fuzzy strict components of associated to in the general case and for the three particular cases where

Example 4.6. If satisfying then Theorem 4.5 implies that has an optimal strict component defined by, ,
If then the optimal strict component of is defined by, , This version is the one obtained by Dimitrov (see [18] or Proposition 4.1). If then the optimal strict component of is defined by, , If then the optimal strict component of is defined by, ,

It is interesting to give some cases of where the family of intuitionistic fuzzy strict components of has a unique element (i.e., becomes the optimal intuitionistic fuzzy strict component).

The following result specifies that we have a unique intuitionistic fuzzy strict component of an IFR if is a strict t-conorm satisfying or

Corollary 4.7. Let be an IFR; and are two IFRs.
If is a strict t-conorm satisfying or thus the two following statements are equivalent:(1) and are โ€œindifference of R" and โ€œstrict component of " associated to respectively.(2) and are, respectively, defined by, ,

The following result shows that when the IFR becomes a FR, the previous theorem becomes the factorization established by Fono and Andjiga (see [7, Proposition , page 378]).

Corollary 4.8. Let , be an IFR; and are two IFRs.
If and are dual and becomes a FR, then the two following statements are equivalent:(1) and are โ€œindifference of " and โ€œstrict component of " associated to , respectively.(2) and are, respectively, defined by, (i)(ii);(iii), and is a solution of (4.9).

In this case, โ€œindifference of an IFR" and โ€œstrict component of an IFR" become โ€œindifference of a FR" and โ€œstrict component of a FR" associated to , respectively.

In the rest of the paper, we study two properties of a given strict component of an IFR.

In literature of (binary) crisp relations, it is well-known that the unique strict component of a given reflexive, complete, and transitive crisp relation satisfies those two interesting and usual properties, namely, pos-transitivity, that is, and negative transitivity, that is,

Fono and Andjiga [7] showed that this result is no true in the fuzzy case. More precisely, they introduced fuzzy versions of these properties (see [7, Definition , page 379]), showed that some strict components violate these fuzzy versions (see [7, Example , page 383]). They determined necessary and sufficient conditions on a reflexive, weakly complete and -transitive FR such that a regular fuzzy strict component of satisfies each of these properties (see [7, Propositions and , page 381]).

Following this line, the aim of the sequel is to (i) introduce a version of pos-transitivity for IFRs and a version of negative transitivity for IFRs and (ii) determine necessary and sufficient conditions on a given -transitive IFR under which a strict component of satisfies the introduced properties.

5. Properties of a Strict Component of an IFR

5.1. Definitions and Examples of Properties, and New Conditions on an IFR

Definition 5.1. Let be an IFR, and let be a strict component of
(1) is pos-transitive if (2) is negative transitive if ,

Let us give the following remark on these definitions.

Remark 5.2. As is regular, we can rewrite the pos-transitivity as follows: ,
As is regular, the negative transitivity is equivalent to the following conjunction: , Since is -symmetric, then are equivalent to respectively.

One of the main questions is to wonder if a strict component of a given IFR, which is not a FR, satisfies each of these two properties.

In the following, we justify that there exists an IFR (distinct to FRs) such that some strict components of violate each of these properties.

Example 5.3. Let and (thus by Proposition 2.10, satisfies condition
(1) We determine an IFR on such that there exists a strict component of which violates pos-transitivity, (i.e., satisfies: there exists such that
Let be defined by, ; ; .
Clearly, is reflexive, weakly complete, and -symmetric. By Theorem 4.5, has an optimal strict component defined by (4.15).
We have: ; ; and , whereas and .
In other words, is strictly preferred to y (since and ), and is strictly preferred to (since and ), but is not strictly preferred to (since and ).
Hence violates pos-transitivity.
(2) We determine an IFR on such that there exists a strict component of which violates negative transitivity, (i.e., satisfies: there exists such that
Let be defined by, ; ; .
Clearly, is reflexive, weakly complete, and -symmetric. By Theorem 4.5, has an optimal strict component defined by (4.15).
We have and , whereas , and .
In other words, is strictly preferred to (since and but is not strictly preferred to (since and ), and is not strictly preferred to (since and ).
Hence violates negative transitivity.

This enables us to determine necessary and sufficient conditions on an IFR such that a given strict component of is pos-transitive and negative transitive. For that we introduce the following conditions.

Definition 5.4. Let be an IFR.
()(i) satisfies condition if , (ii) satisfies condition if , (i) satisfies condition if , (ii) satisfies condition if ,

The next result shows that a strongly complete IFR satisfies the previous conditions.

Proposition 5.5. Let be an IFR.
If is strongly complete, then satisfies conditions , and .

5.2. Characterization of Some Properties of a Strict Component of an IFR

We now establish, using and , our second main result which determines all -transitive IFRs whose strict components are pos-transitive.

Theorem 5.6. Let be a -transitive IFR, and let be a strict component of Then

In the particular case where is strongly complete, the previous result becomes as follows:

Corollary 5.7. Let be a -transitive IFR, and let be a strict component of
If is strongly complete, then is pos-transitive.

Given a -transitive IFR , the next result establishes an equivalence between conditions and and two properties of .

Lemma 5.8. Let be a -transitive IFR, and let be a strict component of
The two following statements are equivalent:
(1) satisfies condition or condition ;(2)

It is important to notice that as is regular and is -symmetric, we can rewrite (5.15) as follows:

The third and last main result of our paper determines all -transitive IFRs whose strict components are negative transitive.

Theorem 5.9. Let be a -transitive IFR, and let be a strict component of . Then

In the particular case where is strongly complete, the previous result becomes as follows:

Corollary 5.10. Let be a -transitive IFR, and let be a strict component of .
If is strongly complete, then is negative transitive.

6. Concluding Remarks

In this paper, we establish a characterization of the -transitivity of We also establish a general factorization of an intuitionistic fuzzy binary relation when the union is defined by a continuous t-representable intuitionistic fuzzy t-conorm satisfying condition This factorization gives a family of regular strict components. Furthermore, given an IFR , we introduce two conditions and (or equivalently and . And we show that, when is -transitive, these conditions are necessary and sufficient to obtain pos-transitivity and negative transitivity of a given strict component of .

An open problem is to apply these results especially in social choice theory when individual and social preferences are modelled by reflexive, weakly complete, and -transitive IFRs. Another open problem is to study the properties of the class of continuous t-representable intuitionistic fuzzy t-conorms satisfying condition .

Appendix

The Proofs of our Results

Proof of Proposition 2.7. Let Since then . Set , we have โ€‰โ€‰โ€‰.
The proof is obvious.

Proof of Lemma 2.8. Let . Set = and . That is to show that .
Since and is a complete lattice, and and are continuous functions on the compact , then the definition of lower limit in gives
Otherwise, with the second result of Proposition 2.1, we have We distinguish three cases.
(i)If and then with the third result of Proposition 2.1, we have and . This implies . Thus, Hence .(ii)If ( and ) or ( and ), then with the third result of Proposition 2.1, it is easy to show that Hence .(iii)If and , then with the third result of Proposition 2.1, , and . We distinguish two cases.(a)If , thus Hence .(b)If , thus Hence .
Finally, we obtain .
The proof of the second result is analogous to the previous one.

Proof of Proposition 2.10. Let such that
(i)Since and with Example 2.5, it is obvious to show that satisfies condition .(ii)Assume that and let us show that satisfies condition that is, It suffices to show that . Set .(a) Since and the mapping is decreasing, then that is, . (b)Since , we obtain that is, (c)Since the previous inequality becomes that is, that is, that is, . And we have .(iii)The proof of the case is similar to the previous one.
Let be a restriction of on Assume that and are dual and show that satisfies . Let such that Let us show that
Since and are are dual, then . Thus, Hence the result.

Proof of Proposition 3.4. Suppose that is -complete and let us show that is -complete.
Let such that Thus and . Since and , we have and Hence and

Proof of Proposition 3.9. For all , we have the following.
(1)Let us show that . In fact, , = , = since is a t-norm on (a)Let us show that . In fact, = min(,โ€‰, ). Since, , and is a t-norm in , then (b)The proofs of the assertions and are analogous to the previous ones.(2)The proof of the last result is deduced from the second result of Lemma 2.8.

Proof of Corollary 3.11. Assume that is strongly complete.
(1)Assume also that satisfies (3.9). And in the three cases, we have , and . This implies , , and , , . And we obtain , and Thus and .(2)Assume that satisfies (3.11). Thus and ( or Thus,
Assume to the contrary that We have . Hence and This contradicts the assertion or .
Let us show that and
Proposition 3.9 implies that
By definition, and .
Analogously, and . Thus , and .

Proof of Corollary 3.12. Assume that and are dual and is a FR. Let .(i) Let us show that
By definition, and . Since is a FR, we have and . Otherwise, since and are dual, we have . Thus . Hence the result.
(ii) The proof of equality is analogous to the previous one.(iii) Let us show that With the previous proposition, . Since is a FR, we have , , and . Otherwise, since and are dual, we have and . Thus .
Otherwise, , , , , , , = , , , , = , , ,โ€‰, , = , = . Hence the result.
(iv) The proof of the equality is analogous to the previous one.
The proof of the last result is obvious.

Proof of Lemma 3.13. (i)(ii): Assume that is -transitive on and show that (3.16).
Since is -transitive on , then we have the following twelve inequalities: Let us show that .
By definition of , the two first inequalities of (iii) of (A.10) imply . And the second inequalities of (i) give that is, Thus,
Otherwise, the third inequality of (iii) gives . The third inequality of (i) gives Thus, . Hence the result.
With the two first inequalities of (iv) of (A.10), the second inequality of (ii) of (A.10), the third inequality of (iv) of (A.10), and the third inequality of (ii) of (A.10), we show analogously that .
With the two first inequalities of (i) of (A.10) and the third inequality of (i) of (A.10), we show analogously that .
With the two first inequalities of (ii) of (A.10) and the third inequality of (ii) of (A.10), we show analogously that . Hence the result.
(ii)(i): Assume (3.16), and let us show that is -transitive on . That is to show the twelve inequalities of (A.10).
The assertion implies , and . Thus, the second result of Proposition 2.1 and the last inequalities imply and . Hence (iv) of (A.10).
Analogously, the assertion and the second result of Proposition 2.1 imply (iii) of (A.10); the assertion and the second result of Proposition 2.1 imply (i) of (A.10); the assertion , and the second result of Proposition 2.1 imply (ii) of (A.10).

Proof of Lemma 4.2. Let .
Let us show that
Since and is symmetric, thus and . We distinguish two cases.
(i) Suppose that or ( and ).
The perfect antisymmetric of implies . Since is a t-norm, . This last equality and (i) of (2.3) imply . Thus,
(ii) Suppose that and .
Since is a t-norm and is symmetric, This equality and (i) of (2.3) imply Thus,
The proof of the equality is similar to the previous one.
() Let us show that .
Since , thus and .
: Assume to the contrary that and .
Since is perfect antisymmetric and , we have . Thus . Since the previous result gives Since is symmetric, the two previous equalities imply . The -symmetric of and the previous equality imply . Thus, since is simple, the two previous equalities imply which contradicts the hypothesis . Finally, .
(): The proof of converse is obvious.
The proof of the equivalence is analogous to the previous one.

Proof of Lemma 4.4. Suppose that and .
(i) Consider the function defined over by , thus and . is continuous and monotone because is continuous and monotone. Then takes all values between and . In particular, has the value for . Thus (4.9) has at least a solution.
By considering the function defined over by , we analogously show that (4.9) has at least a solution.
(ii) Let us show that each solution of (4.9) is strictly positive. Let be a solution of (4.9).
Assume to the contrary that . Thus, that is, which contradicts . And we have .
Let us show that each solution of (4.9) is least than . Let be a solution of (4.9). Assume to the contrary that . Thus, that is, which contradicts . And we have .
(iii) Assume that satisfies condition We can remark by of Proposition 2.1 that and . Since is -symmetric, Because satisfies condition , then , and the previous equality imply Hence is a solution of (4.8).(iv) Assume that satisfies condition , and let us show that is the lowest solution for (4.9)
Consider another solution of (4.9)(). Thus we have which implies . Since , we deduce that
We analogously show that is the upper solution for (4.9)
(v) If we easily show that is the unique solution of (4.8).
Suppose that is a strict t-conorm on satisfying condition
The previous functions and defined in (i) are, respectively, the bijections from to and from to . We easily show that is the unique solution of (4.8).

Proof of Theorem 4.5. (1)(2): Lemma 4.2 implies .
Let us show . , suppose that and .
(iii) of Lemma 4.4 implies that (4.8) has at least one solution. Set one of these solutions. Thus is a solution of (4.9)(), and is a solution of (4.9)(). With (ii) of Lemma 4.4, we have and Since the equality is equivalent to equation , hence and .
For the case where and we easily show that Lemma 4.2 implies that and .
(2)(1): Let .
implies that , and which show that is symmetric.
Let us show that that is, and . Since is -symmetric, we distinguish two cases.
(a)If and , thus implies , and , and the definition of gives and . We have and .(b)If and , thus implies that is a solution of (4.9), and is a solution of (4.9); we have and . Furthermore, as , and , implies and . Then and .
It is easy to show that P is simple and is perfect antisymmetric.

Proof of Corollary 4.7. The proof of this corollary is deduced from Theorem 4.5 and the last result of Lemma 4.4.

Proof of Corollary 4.8. The proof is deduced from Lemma 4.2, Theorem 4.5, and the last result of Proposition 3.9.

Proof of Proposition 5.5. Let . Since is strongly complete, Corollary 3.11 implies and .

Proof of Theorem 5.6. As is -symmetric, (i) of (5.3) and (ii) of (5.3) are equivalent. Therefore, to show (5.3) means to show (i) of (5.3) or (ii) of (5.3).
: We distinguish two cases.
(1)Suppose that satisfies condition , and let us show that is pos-transitive. We show (i) of (5.3). Let such that and Let us show that . Since is -transitive on , Lemma 3.13 implies We distinguish two cases.(a)Suppose that or or ; thus (A.11) implies .(b)Suppose that and ; thus, since , and satisfies condition , we deduce that (2)With Lemma 4.2, the proof is analogous to the previous one.
Suppose that is pos-transitive, and let us show that satisfies or .
Since is pos-transitive, we have (5.3), that is, (i) of (5.3) or (ii) of (5.3). We distinguish two cases.
(a)Suppose (ii) of (5.3), and let us show that satisfies Suppose that verifies and Let us show that Since satisfies the two previous inequalities and of (5.3) imply (b)With (i) of (5.3), we show analogously that satisfies

Proof of Corollary 5.7. Since is strongly complete, then Proposition 5.5 implies that satisfies condition . Hence, Theorem 5.6 implies that is pos-transitive.

Proof of Lemma 5.8. To establish (5.15) is equivalent to establish (5.16).
We remark that as is -symmetric, (i) of (5.16) and (ii) of (5.16) are equivalent.
(1)(2): We distinguish two cases.
(1)Suppose that satisfies condition , and let us show (5.16). We show (i) of (5.16). Let such that Let us show that . Since is -transitive on , Lemma 3.13 implies (A.11). We distinguish two cases.(a)Suppose that or or ; thus (A.11) implies .(b)Suppose that and With (A.14), the condition implies that (2)Suppose that satisfies condition , and let us show (5.16). We show (ii) of (5.16). Let such that Let us show that Since is -transitive on , Lemma 4.2 implies We distinguish two cases.(a)Suppose that or or ; thus (A.16) implies that .(b)Suppose that and With (A.15), the condition implies that
(2)(1) Suppose (5.16), and let us show that satisfies or . We distinguish two cases.
(a)Suppose (i) of (5.16), and let us show that satisfies Suppose (A.14), and Let us show that With (A.14), (i) of (5.16) implies (b)With (ii) of (5.16), we show analogously that satisfies

Proof of Theorem 5.9. As is -symmetric, Remark 5.2 implies that (5.4) and (5.5) are equivalent. Therefore, to show (5.4) means to show (5.4) or (5.5).
: We distinguish two cases.
(1)Suppose that satisfies condition and , and let us show that is negative transitive. We show (5.4). Let . We distinguish three cases.(a)Suppose and let us show that . Since satisfies condition , Theorem 5.6 implies that is pos-transitive. Thus, and the pos-transitivity of imply that Hence .(b)Suppose (A.14) and let us show that . Since satisfies condition and (A.14), then Lemma 5.8 implies that Hence .(c)Suppose that and and let us show that . Assume to the contrary that . Thus, and , that is, Since satisfies condition and then Lemma 5.8 implies that which contradicts the hypothesis .(2)Suppose that satisfies condition and , and let us show that is negative transitive. We show (5.5). Let . We distinguish three cases.(a)Suppose that verifies and let us show that . Since satisfies condition , Theorem 5.6 implies that is pos-transitive. Thus, and the pos-transitivity of imply that . Hence .(b)Suppose (A.15), and let us show that . Since satisfies condition and (A.15), then Lemma 5.8 implies that . Hence .(c)Suppose that and ; and let us show that . Assume to the contrary that . Thus, Since satisfies condition and then Lemma 5.8 implies which contradicts hypothesis .
Suppose that is negative transitive, and let us show that satisfies ( and ) or ( and ).
Since is negative transitive, we have (5.4) and (5.5), that is, (5.4) or (5.5) as is -symmetric. We distinguish two cases.
(i)Suppose (5.4), and let us show that satisfies and . Suppose that and (3.9). Let us show that . In fact, (3.9) and (5.4) imply . Assume to the contrary that . With (3.9), we distinguish two cases.(a)If and ; thus we have and . Hence the negative transitivity of implies which contradicts the hypothesis .(b)If and ; thus we have and . Hence the negative transitivity of implies which contradicts the hypothesis .(ii)Suppose (5.5) and let us show that satisfies and . Suppose (3.11) and Let us show that . In fact, (3.11) and (5.5) imply . Assume to the contrary that . With (3.11), we distinguish two cases.(a)If and ; thus we have and . Hence the negative transitivity of implies which contradicts the hypothesis .(b)If and ; thus we have and . Hence the negative transitivity of implies which contradicts the hypothesis .

Proof of Corollary 5.10. The proof is deduced from Proposition 5.5 and Theorem 5.9.

Acknowledgments

The authors are thankful to the members of Laboratoire MASS and those of CREM for their help and advice. The second author thanks French Governement and AUF (Agence Universitaire de la Francophonie). This work was achieved when he was student at Universitรฉ de Caen Basse-Normandie France, under the research grants โ€œBourse de formation ร  la recherche de la Francophonie 2007-2008โ€ and โ€œBourse de doctorat du SCAC-Yaoundรฉ 2007-2008โ€.