Abstract

We consider a two-period model in which a continuum of agents trade in a context of costly information acquisition and systematic heterogeneous expectations biases. Because of systematic biases agents are supposed not to learn from others' decisions. In a previous work under somehow strong technical assumptions a market equilibrium was proved to exist and the supply and demand functions were proved to be strictly monotonic with respect to the price. Here we extend these results under very weak technical assumptions. We also prove that the equilibrium price maximizes the trading volume and further additional properties (such as the antimonotonicity of the trading volume with respect to the marginal information price).

1. Introduction

We consider a continuum of agents that act in a two-period () market consisting of a single asset of value . The value is constant and deterministic but unknown to the agents. Each agent constructs an estimation for in the form of a normal random variable with known mean and variance. The numerical value of the mean, which is not necessarily and as such can be interpreted as a systematic bias, is given by the estimation method and cannot be changed. However, the variance can be reduced at time by paying a cost, which is a known deterministic function of the variance to be attained. Each agent uses a CARA utility function and constructs the function mapping each triplet (consisting of the market price, the estimation mean, and the estimation variance) to the optimal number of units to trade. The sum of all such functions from all agents results at time in aggregate market demand and supply functions; the price of the asset is chosen to clear the market (we prove in particular that such a price exists and is unique). This price can be different from the real value and in practice it will. The agents close their position at final time . This paper investigates the following questions: existence of an equilibrium, continuity of supply and demand functions, and interpretation of the equilibrium price as the value maximizing the liquidity (trading volume).

The paper is organized as follows. The rest of this section presents a literature overview. In Section 2 the model is explained and the fundamental Assumption 3 is introduced. In Sections 3 and 3.1, we prove the existence of an equilibrium and important properties of the liquidity (here defined as the transaction volume); in particular we prove that the equilibrium price maximizes the trading volume. We apply our results to a Grossmann-Stiglitz framework in Section 4. Finally, in Section 5 we show that the liquidity is inversely correlated with the marginal price of information.

1.1. Literature Overview

The model has two important ingredients:(i)the existence of heterogeneous beliefs (or expectations) biases among a continuum of agents;(ii)the fact that the information is costly (the literature refers to “information acquisition” cost).

There are many models that explain how disagreements between agent estimations generate investment decisions and trading volume. The importance of the heterogeneity of opinions on the future value of a financial instrument and its use in speculation has been recognized as early as Keynes (see [1]) who invokes the “beauty contest” metaphor to explain how speculators infer the future (consensus) price.

A model of speculative trading in a large economy with a continuum of agents with heterogeneous beliefs was presented in [2, 3] (see also the references within). They demonstrate the existence of price amplification effects and show that the equilibrium prices can be different from the rational expectation equilibrium price. It is also shown that trading volume is positively related to the directions of price changes and they explain the recurrent presence of diverse beliefs. We also refer to [4] and references within for a survey on how heterogeneous beliefs among agents generate speculation and trading.

The difference-of-opinion approach (see [5, 6]) does not consider “noise agents” but on the contrary obtains diverse posterior beliefs from the differences in the way agents interpret common information. They focus on the implications of the dispersion in beliefs on the price level or direction. Yet another different method explains diverse posterior beliefs by relaxing the assumption of a common prior distribution (see [7]); the authors also model the learning process which enables a convergence towards a common estimation when more information is available. Such a framework was invoked for modeling asset pricing during initial public offerings, but not for other speculative circumstances. Finally, Pagano [8] analyze the implications of low liquidity in a market and propose appropriate incentive schemes to shift the market to an equilibrium characterized by a higher number of transactions.

An important advance has been to recognize that the dynamics of the information gathering is important; it was thus established how the presence of private information and noise (liquidity) agents interact with market price and volume (see, e.g., [911], for recent related endeavors). More specifically it was recognized (the so called “Grossman-Stiglitz paradox”) that it is not always optimal for the agents to obtain all the information on a particular asset. This remark is of importance in our paper in the following because, as explained in Section 2, our model allows each agent to choose his level of precision related to the estimation of the true value of the traded asset. In the classical paper of [12] and in subsequent related works [1318] a framework is proposed where the information is costly and agents can pay more to lower their uncertainty on the future value of the risky asset. Verrechia derives a closed form solution which requires some particular assumptions. These include the convexity of the cost function with respect to the precision (the precision being the inverse of the estimate’s variance). On the contrary our cost function is here only lower semicontinuous. Our approach also differs in a more fundamental way in that we suppose that heterogeneity of estimations is given but arbitrary, that is, not centered around the correct price. Moreover, the Verrecchia model relies on the heterogeneity of risk tolerances in the CARA utility function while in our work the price formation mechanism does not require such an assumption, the heterogeneity in estimations being enough. Also, in this model, the endowments of the agents do not play any role and in particular are not required to obtain an equilibrium. The paper extends a previous work [19] where stronger technical assumptions were invoked.

2. The Model

We consider a two-period model, and , in which a risky security of value is traded. The value is unknown to the agents and each participant in the market constructs an estimate for at , being a random variable. For simplicity, we suppose that has a normal distribution and that and are independent if and are two distinct agents (this independence assumption is motivated by the existence of an individual bias for each agent as explained below). Also, we assume that the mean and the variance of are, respectively, given by and , both mean and variance being known to the agent . As in [12] we work with the precision instead of the variance .

Many estimation procedures can output results in the form of a normal variable with known mean and variance, the most known example being a Kalman-Bucy filter; see [20] for details.

Note that we do not model here the riskless security, but everything works as if the numeraire was the riskless security; from a technical point of view this allows setting the interest rate to zero.

An important remark is that each agent has his own bias attached to the estimate because he has his own procedure to interpret the available information. It may be due to personal optimism or pessimism (e.g., the agent is a “bull” or “bear”) or may be correlated with some exogenous factors, such as overall economic outlooks, commodities evolution, and geopolitical factors, which each agent interprets with a specific systematic bias. See also the cited references for additional discussion on how agents interpret the information they obtain. We assume that the bias of agent does not depend on the precision to be attained and only depends on the agent; the value associated to an agent is known only by him. The agent does not influence in any way during the process of forecasting; his forecasting process is not influenced by other agents’ decisions; that is, there is no collective learning in this model. Hence, two different agents and have generically different biases and and thus different estimation averages and . This is not a collateral property of the model. It is instead the mere reason for which the agents trade. They trade because they have different (heterogeneous) expectations on the final value of the security.

We define to be the distribution of among the agents; neither the law of the distribution nor any moments or statistics is known by the agents. We also introduce the expected value with respect to , which is denoted by ; see also [21] for related works on empirical estimation of such a distribution . We do not assume the law of to be normal or have particular properties (except technical Assumption 9).

From a theoretical point of view, it is interesting to explore the case when . This means that the average estimate is , so that the agents are neither overpricing nor underpricing the security with respect to its (unknown) value. However, we will see that this does not necessarily indicate that the market price is .

The only parameter the agent can control is the accuracy of the result, that is, the precision . However, this has a cost: the agent has to pay to obtain the precision . The precision cost function is defined on positive numbers but if needed we set by convention for any . See also [22] for an example involving a power function and [18] for a structural model to motivate such a function.

Such a model is relevant in the case of high expense for information sources, for instance, news broadcasting fees. The expense also involves the reward of research personnel or the need for more accurate computer simulations.

Based on his estimations the agent decides at time to trade a quantity of security units. When is positive, the agent is long, so he buys the security, whereas when is negative, he is short; he sells it.

Hence, each agent is characterized by three parameters: his mean estimate , the precision of the estimate (that comes at a cost ), and the quantity of traded units, .

The agents buy or sell the security at time by formulating demand and supply functions depending on the price. The market price at time is chosen to clear the aggregate total demand/supply.

Remark 1. The price that clears the market is also called market equilibrium price. Note however that the uniqueness of the equilibrium is, at this stage, not proved.

We set the investment horizon of all agents to be the final time which is the time when each agent liquidates his initial position. Each agent supposes that this final transaction takes place at a price in agreement with his initial estimation.

In order to describe the model for the market price, we introduce for any price the basic notions of total supply and total demand defined as where for any real number we define , .

A price such that is said to clear the market. From the definition of and in (1) this is equivalent to saying that ; that is, at the price , the overall (signed) demand is zero. Note that such a price may not exist or may not be unique. Hence, one of the goals of the paper is to prove existence and uniqueness of .

The transaction volume at some price is the number of units that can be exchanged at that price and is defined as follows:

A price for which reaches its maximum is of particular interest because it maximizes the total number of asset units being exchanged. Note that such a price may not exist and may also be nonunique.

Let us recall the following result (see [19] for the proof).

Theorem 2. Suppose that functions , are continuous and positive, , and . Consider the following.(A)If is increasing, not identically zero, and is decreasing, then there exists at least one price such that ; moreover for all .(B)In addition to previous assumptions suppose that is strictly increasing and , whereas is strictly decreasing and such that . Then the following statements are true.(1)There exists a unique such that .(2)There exists a unique such that for all .(3)Moreover .

Recall that is said to be lower semicontinuous (denoted by “l.s.c.”) if for any A function such that is l.s.c. is said to be upper semicontinuous (denoted by “u.s.c.”).

For any function we define In particular . Denote by its positive part.

Let us introduce an important assumption of this paper.

Assumption 3. We say that a function satisfies Assumption 3 if , is lower semicontinuous, and there exists such that

Remark 4. The quantity represents the residual cost, when precision approaches zero, to enter the market. It is not related to the precision (because there is none in the limit) but to the fixed costs to trade on the market (independent of the quantity). A market with infinite fixed costs is not realistic.
The assumption implies, by lower semicontinuity, that and is realistic in that it demands that the price of zero precision be finite.

In order to model the choices of the agents, we consider that the agents maximize a CARA-type expected utility function (see [23]); that is, if the output is the random variable , they maximize . Note that if is a normal random variable with mean and variance , then maximizing is equivalent to maximizing the mean-variance utility function . We refer to (6) for the treatment of degenerate normal variables with infinite variance. The parameter is called the risk aversion coefficient. Note that all agents have here the same utility function; see for instance [24, 25] who argue that differences in preferences are not a major factor in explaining the magnitude of trade in speculative markets.

Of course, the expected wealth of the agent at time is a function of and . It is computed under the assumption that each agent enters the transaction (buys or sells) at time at the market price and exits the transaction (sells or buys) at time at a price coherent with his estimation; that is, we condition on the available information at time . Thus, for a given price , which is not necessarily equal to the market equilibrium price , the average expected wealth at time of the agent denoted by is given by . The variance of the wealth, denoted by , is given by .

Thus, for a given price (not necessarily the market equilibrium price ) the fact that agent optimizes his CARA utility function is equivalent to saying that he optimizes with respect to and his mean-variance utility:

3. Existence of the Transaction Volume

Each agent is characterized by his own bias . The agents consider the market price as being fixed, which means they cannot influence it directly. They do not know any statistics on so the market price is not directly informative, but the acquired information is. Therefore, their strategy depend on two values: the bias and the market price .

Under Assumption 3, the agent chooses the optimal pair of precision and demand/supply , that is, the value of the pair maximizing the following expression: so that

Let and let be the function defined by . To simplify the notations we sometimes write only , , or instead of and / instead of /; likewise stands for .

Lemma 5. Under Assumption 3, for any and , there exists a pair such that (8) is satisfied.

Proof. Since satisfies Assumption 3, there exists and some positive constant such that for all . In particular for we have . Since is l.s.c. then is u.s.c.; it follows that attains its maximum on in the interval . We set to be one such maximum (it may not be unique) and set .
Note that implies ; thus
When , one has
Let . Since is a parabola with negative leading coefficient with respect to its first argument, it follows that

Remark 6. Note that the formula is completely compatible with previous works, see [26] p575, although here we have no assumption on budget constraints and the risk-less interest rate is set to zero.

In order to prove the existence of an equilibrium we need the following auxiliary results (Lemmas 711).

Lemma 7. Under Assumption 3, let , be such that , where . Then . One says that is increasing with respect to . In particular, for fixed , one has the following:(i) is increasing with respect to on the interval ;(ii) is decreasing with respect to on the interval .

Proof. Let , for . Recall that optimizes with respect to . Then Thus, and hence , which gives the conclusion.

Lemma 8. Under Assumption 3, let , , be a sequence such that but does not converge to . The set of such is at most countable. In particular, if is fixed, then the set of such that is discontinuous with respect to is countable. An analogous result holds if is fixed.

Proof. Let , for . Without loss of generality, we only investigate the case when the sequence converges decreasingly to . Then, we have , .
Since does not converge to , let . Note that and , . Also recall that Yet, since is u.s.c., and for fixed , converges to . In the limit when , it holds that This implies that is also a maximum for . From this we deduce that has at least two distinct maximums, and .
Let be such that has at least two distinct minimums and with ; we associate to a rational number such that . Take and such that ; to fix notations suppose . Then by the previous result ; moreover ; that is, . Thus the set of such that has at least two distinct minimums is of cardinality smaller than the cardinality of , that is, at most countable. Since continuity can only fail when has nonunique maximum, the conclusion follows.

Assumption 9. We say that satisfies Assumption 9 if is absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure and

Lemma 10. Let and (or in short notation and when function is implicit) be defined by Then under Assumptions 3 and 9   and are finite, continuous, and monotonic. Moreover .

Proof. To prove that and are finite we recall that the maximum of is attained in the interval ; that is, . Recalling that it follows that both integrals are bounded (modulo some constant) by ; that is, and are finite for all .
Let be a sequence increasingly converging to . For any , the set of such that is discontinuous is at most countable. Denote it by . Let . is also clearly countable and thus .
Let and . Then , for all with the possible exception of the null set . Also, the sequence is increasing.
Then from the Beppo-Levi theorem, the following holds: This proves sequential continuity of and thus its continuity. The monotonicity is a consequence of the monotonicity of . This result also holds for the demand , recalling that is increasing and lower-bounded.
The property is trivial. To prove it is sufficient to use the above upper bound for and .

Recall that is increasing on but in order to use Theorem 2 we need to prove its strict monotonicity.

Lemma 11. Under Assumptions 3 and 9 and supposing the following hold: (1) is strictly increasing on ;(2);(3);(4) is strictly decreasing on ;(5)if , then ;(6).

Remark 12. The assumption will be relaxed in Section 3.1, cf. Theorem 18.

Proof. Note that implies in particular continuity of at . Letting and be such that , Since is increasing if , Hence, Note that implies that . So, in order to prove the strict inequality in the estimation above, it is sufficient to prove that with in the support of . Yet Therefore we only need to prove that there exists such that with in the support of . A sufficient condition is that the upper limit of derivative of at be strictly positive. This means which is equivalent to . Recalling that , the latter condition can be rewritten as or else , for at least one in the support of . Therefore as soon as is in . This implies strict monotonicity for on and hence also on the interval .
We have already seen that . Moreover since the supply is strictly increasing on and increasing on , it holds that .
For the monotonicity of the demand, let and be such that . Then Since is decreasing for , we have Hence, Note that implies that . For strict inequality it is sufficient to prove that . Using the same arguments as in Lemma 11, we have strict monotonicity as soon as .
Recalling that , the latter condition can be written as or else for at least one in the support of . Therefore, as soon as is in . This yields strict monotonicity of on . Monotonicity also holds on by continuity.
Since , we have so .
Hence, demand is strictly decreasing. Previously we also proved that .

The above results can be summarized in the following.

Theorem 13. Under Assumptions 3 and 9 and supposing the following hold:(A)there exists at least a such that , ; moreover ;(B)suppose that ; then(1)the functions and are well defined,(2)there exists a unique such that , . Moreover is the unique solution of the equation .

Note that the results of [19] are a special case of this Theorem (any convex function is l.s.c.).

Remark 14. If , then and , (see Figure 1).

Remark 15. Since we assume the distribution to be absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure, it holds that . Thus one can always find a critical value defined as such that for any , the assumptions of Theorem 13 are satisfied; that is, there exists a market price maximizing the volume and clearing the market. On the contrary there exists no such market price for . The results of [19] are a special case of this remark. In fact, under the assumptions given in [19], and thus .
The critical value can be interpreted as the maximum risk aversion allowing the market to function. If the risk aversion becomes larger than the critical value, the market stops and a liquidity crisis occurs. In the latter case, several actions can be proposed to stop the liquidity crisis:(i)lowering the perception of risk, that is, lower the of the agents;(ii)making higher by lowering , that is, lower the marginal cost of information around zero precision. In other words, eliminate any entry barriers for new agents on that market by largely spreading information about the real situation of the asset ;(iii)making higher by increasing . This means inviting to the market agents with new, different evaluation procedures. This can be carried out for instance by eliminating any entry barrier for newcomers when they have a different background and different evaluation procedures.

3.1. Necessary and Sufficient Results for General Functions

In this section we relax the assumption . For any function we denote by the Legendre-Fenchel transform (cf. [27]) of and by the Legendre-Fenchel transform applied twice, and so on. We show in this section that the twice Legendre-Fenchel transform of the cost function has remarkable properties; that is, we can replace by for any practical means. In particular this means that from a technical point of view one can suppose that is convex even if the actual function is not.

Theorem 16. Let be a function satisfying Assumption 3. The following properties hold for :(1) also satisfies Assumption 3;(2)except for a countable set of values , one has (3)as a consequence

Proof. To prove point we recall that is a convex function and , . In particular is l.s.c. and continuous in . Let us now check the growth condition and take that satisfies Assumption 3 for . Take also as the constant in Lemma 5; that is, for all . Consider now the function Then it is straightforward to see that where ; of course and is l.s.c. Then we also have the inequality . But obviously . Hence .
To prove point we recall that the cost function is used only as a part of the function . Let us take a point and a minimum of . This implies which can also be written as That is, as stated in [27], the function has a supporting hyperplane at . Since has a supporting hyperplane at this implies that ; recall that is the convex hull of , that is, the largest convex function such that . Hence, recall that for any function , We thus obtained that is a maximum of .
Therefore, if is replaced by , the minimization problem involving gives the same solution, except possibly a countable set of values where the maximum is attained (either for or ) in more than one point.
Point is a mere consequence of point .

For all purposes of calculating aggregate supply and demand we can thus replace by , that is, replace by its convex hull. Therefore, one can work as if was convex.

Remark 17. This result is particularly useful when because in this situation . Then one cannot use the previous results that guarantee the uniqueness of the market clearing price. When is replaced by it can be shown that becomes finite and the results apply for . However Theorem 16 allows recovering the results for the initial function and obtaining the full information on the supply and demand functions and on the market price.

We obtain the following.

Theorem 18. Suppose that Assumptions 3 and 9 are satisfied. Then there exists at least one price such that This price also satisfies
Furthermore, consider the following.(I)If there exists such that , then and are always strictly positive and strictly monotonic, . Moreover the price satisfying (35) is unique.(II)Suppose now that , ; then the following hold:(a)(alternative 1) suppose that ; then(i)the functions and are well defined,(ii)the price satisfying (35) is unique and ; is also the unique solution of (36);(b)(alternative 2) if on the contrary one supposes that then , .

Proof. We prove first point (I). If , then for all , ; thus for all . As a consequence we obtain for all and the same for . For strict monotonicity it suffices to use same arguments as in the proof of Lemma 11. Of course, due to Lemma 10.
The point (IIa) follows from the discussion above.
To prove (IIb) we need to analyze in greater detail the values of and . If we consider , then (we exclude the null measure set of where more than one maximum can exists; that is, we can suppose the inequality to be strict); hence or, for some , Since is convex we have for arbitrary , . But this means ; that is, .
If is always zero, the conclusion is reached. Suppose now exists such that ; then at least some in the support of exists such that and ; the three conditions imply Moreover, we have for .
From (40) and (37), we conclude that A similar reasoning as the above shows that for . Therefore for any either or and the conclusion follows.

In general, the price has an implicit dependence on the cost function with no particular properties. But when the distribution is completely symmetric around some particular value ; we obtain the following result.

Theorem 19. Suppose that Assumptions 3 and 9 are satisfied and there exists such that (with the convention that is null on ); then one can take in Theorem 18  .

Proof. The proof follows from the remark that, except possibly for a null measure set of values , the function is symmetric around ; that is, ; thus is antisymmetric. Since the distribution is symmetric then .

4. An Application: The Grossman-Stiglitz Framework

We follow [9] to analyze a classical situation where costly information can be used to lower the uncertainty of the estimation. Note however that in the cited work the equilibrium is reached without modeling the variations in supply and in the absence of the distribution .

In the Grossman-Stiglitz model agents can either pay nothing and have a precision or pay a fixed cost to gain precision up to level . This leads to the function The function does not satisfy assumption in [19] and as such the result therein cannot be used. It however satisfies the Assumption 3; thus using the Theorem 18 we can replace with the following convex function defined as Note that fulfills Assumption 3 with an arbitrary . Suppose that the distribution fulfills the requirements in Assumption 9; absolute continuity with respect to Lebesgue measure and a moment of order (with arbitrary small ) has to exist. Then a (equilibrium) market price exists and is unique. Note that ; thus .

The unsigned demand is The optimal precision is either (first case of (45)) or (second case).

5. Transaction Volume and Marginal Costs

We describe in the following the relationship between the cost function and the trading volume.

Theorem 20. Suppose that and both satisfy Assumption 3 and that satisfies Assumption 9.(A) Assume that Then .(B) In particular if and are such that (all are lateral derivatives) then .

Remark 21. Note that if and are convex, both lateral derivatives are defined at each point and (A) implies (B); thus for practical purposes (cf. also Section 3.1) the point (B) is not weaker than point (A).

Remark 22. If and exist at a certain point , then (47) implies that . Thus, the above result is a generalization of the analogous theorem in [19].

Proof. (A) We first show that, except for a countable set of values , we have . Fix and denote for . Suppose, by contradiction, that ; recall that, since is optimal, Thus Note that we wrote strict inequality in (48) because we exclude the countable set of values where the maximum of is not unique. We do the same for : Thus Combining (49) and (51) we obtain This, however, contradicts (46) for and . Thus, with the possible exception of a countable set of values , we have .
The demand and supply of the agents are monotonic and given for by the formulas
Let be the market price for which supply equals demand for the cost function ; that is, . We further take and .
It has been proved that . Thus, and , . In particular, .
Let be the solution of . Let us prove that . Suppose, on the contrary, that . Then which means that all inequalities in (54) are in fact equalities, in particular and . But we also have which means again that all terms are equal, in particular . Thus which means that is a member of . However as is the minimum of such elements we arrive at a contradiction. It follows that .
Similarly we prove that (see Figure 2). Hence it holds that which concludes the proof.
(B) We prove that (47) implies (46). Of course, it is enough to consider . Denote
Suppose that and exist such that . Note that Then, either or . Iterating the argument we obtain two convergent sequences and with , , and . Up to extracting subsequences only three alternatives exist:(1) for all ,(2) for all ,(3) for all .
Alternative can be reduced to or by noting that since then either or .
We only prove , the proof of being completely similar. When we obtain which is a contradiction. Thus (47) implies (46).

6. Concluding Remarks

The main focus of this work is to establish the existence of an equilibrium and its optimality in terms of trading volumes for the model in Section 2. The results are proved under minimal assumptions on the cost function and a relationship with the convex hull of the cost function is proved. The model can be used to investigate the determinants of the trading volume and may give hints on how to exit a situation when the volume is abnormally low.

Conflict of Interests

The authors declare that there is no conflict of interests regarding the publication of this paper.