Abstract

In real-life games, the consequence or payoff of a strategy profile and a player's belief about the consequence of a strategy profile are often ambiguous, and players may have different optimistic attitudes with respect to a strategy profile. To handle this problem, this paper proposes a decision rule using the Hurwicz criterion and Dempster-Shafer theory. Based on this rule, we introduce a new kind of games, called ambiguous games, and propose a solution concept that is appropriate for this sort of games. Moreover, we also study how the beliefs regarding possible payoffs and optimistic attitudes may affect the solutions of such a game. To illustrate our model, we provide an analysis of a scenario concerning allocating resource of defending and attacking in military contexts.

1. Introduction

Game theory is a powerful tool for analyzing strategic interactions between decision makers in many domains, such as voting, economics, and artificial intelligence. In this theory, a strategic (also called normal form or static) game is used to model a strategic situation, in which it is assumed that the consequence or payoff of a pure strategy profile is determinate or precise. According to this model, many kinds of games and their corresponding solutions can be defined.

In real-life games, the players have to make decisions under ambiguity because there is often only limited information available to the decision maker. In canonical opinion, ambiguity is referred to as a kind of uncertainty that describes situations where decision makers cannot determine a precise probability distribution over the possible consequences of an action [13]. Therefore, in games under ambiguity, the players could only assign a set of possible payoffs, rather than a precise payoff, to a pure strategy profile and have an imprecise probability distribution over this set. Moreover, the players often have some optimistic attitudes (decision attitudes), including optimistic, neutral, and pessimistic, in the decision problems under ambiguity [47]. In view of this, this aforementioned assumption of strategic games seems implausible under ambiguity [810].

To model situations with indeterminate payoffs, one kind of games, known as Bayesian games [11], is constructed based on the assumption that a player’s belief regarding either the other players’ types or their strategy choices is accurate. This means that the player is assumed to have a precise probability distribution over the consequences of a strategy profile. Another kind of games, called fuzzy games [8, 12, 13], assumes instead that the payoffs are fuzzy. This kind of model usually interprets ambiguity as cases where decision makers are uncertain about the probability of each possibility. It is worth noting that players’ optimistic attitudes are not considered in such fuzzy games.

Unlike these two approaches, some researchers have tried to apply some original ideas taken from decision theory to games [1418]. To be more specific, they use nonadditive beliefs (capacities) [19] or multiple prior model (a set of probabilities) to represent ambiguity. Nevertheless, these kinds of work still assume that the consequences in a game are accurate. They thus cannot adequately handle the problem concerning ambiguous consequences and players’ optimistic attitudes. More recently, researchers [20] have proposed a theoretic framework to study games with ambiguous payoffs, where only the case of ambiguity aversion in an interactive situation has been considered.

The aim of this paper is to propose a game-theoretic framework that can deal with imprecise probability theories. Using this theory, we first construct a decision model, in which decision makers are assumed to employ the Hurwicz criterion [21] (a well-known rule that has been used to model decisions under uncertainty [22, 23]) to determine a preference ordering over actions given the interval-valued expected utilities and optimistic attitudes.

Based on this decision-theoretic framework, we then propose a game model, that is, the ambiguous game, which relaxes the assumption that a player’s belief about the consequences of a strategy profile should be precise. In contrast with those frameworks mentioned above, our model allows a player’s belief about the consequence or payoff of each strategy profile to be represented by imprecise probabilities. More importantly, our approach can also be used to model situations where the consequence or payoff of each strategy profile may possibly be ambiguous, and players may have different optimistic attitudes towards ambiguity.

The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. Section 2 briefly reviews some basic concepts and notations of Dempster-Shafer theory, expected utility intervals defined by D-S theory, and the Hurwicz criterion. Section 3 describes the basic elements of strategic games with ambiguous payoffs and investigates the conditions under which the degrees in beliefs regarding possible consequences and optimistic attitudes influence the solutions of an ambiguous game. Section 4 illustrates our approach by considering a scenario concerning allocating resource of defending and attacking in military contexts. Section 5 discusses some related research on the issue of ambiguous games. Finally, in Section 6, we conclude the paper and provide some thoughts about future work.

2. Preliminaries

This section recaps Dempster-Shafer theory [24], the expected utility interval based on this theory [25], and the Hurwicz criterion [21].

Definition 1. Let be a frame of discernment (i.e., the set of states of the world).(i)A function is called a basic probability assignment or a mass function over if and . If , then is said to be a focal element. A mass function is called a simple mass function over if , , where and . In this case, we call a focal mass value.(ii)A function , defined as follows, is a belief function over :

By formula (1), the belief function (called a simple support function) induced by a simple mass function over is given as follows:

The mass function is one of the most important concepts in Dempster-Shafer theory. There exists a natural interpretation of this concept proposed by Shafer and Tversky [26], which interprets a mass function as the degree of reliability for encoding a piece of evidence. To illustrate this, suppose that we randomly draw a ball from an urn containing 300 balls, and we know that 100 of them are red, and the remaining balls might be red (), blue (), or green (). How should we model such a situation where we only have partial information about the proportion of the balls? According to the reliability interpretation, it can be modeled by a simple mass function: , and , where . The mass value encodes that there are 100 balls which are red in the urn, and the value encodes that the remaining 200 balls might be red, blue, or green. It should be noted that , since there is no information concerning the amount of blue and green balls in the urn.

Note that a probability function can be regarded as a special case of mass function. In fact, if and , where is a singleton (i.e., ), then is indeed a probability function because . Nevertheless, we have in general that . That is, the belief function can be interpreted as the lower bound of probability function (i.e., the worst case estimate for probability). Given a simple mass function with support degree to the focal element , then, . Thus, we can interpret the focal mass value as the lower probability of focal element .

The foregoing example shows that Dempster-Shafer theory can represent ambiguous evidence or information in a sensible way. In particular, the simple mass functions (basic mass functions) can be used to model some kinds of ambiguity including the cases of total ignorance and partial information. Regarding the former case, we can assume the support degree to be zero; that is, , , and , which suitably describes the situation of total ignorance. In this case, we call m a vacuous mass function. To represent the case of partial information, let support degree be 1 to a specific subset of the frame of discernment; that is, , . Such a mass function (called a pseudovacuous mass function) can properly model the case of partial information, where we can only be certain that the true event belongs to a subset of the frame of discernment based on the available information.

Now, consider the decision situations, where a decision maker cannot identify the exact consequence that an action will result in, although he can specify the utilities of those possible consequences. In addition, it may be the case that he cannot even determine the probabilities associated with those possible consequences. Using the terminology of Dempster-Shafer theory, the decision maker can only represent such information in terms of a mass function defined over the set of possible consequences. Formally, we can define such decision situations as follows.

Definition 2. A decision problem under ambiguity (or called an ambiguity decision problem) is a 4-tuple of , where(i) is the set of all actions;(ii) is the set of all of consequences of actions;(iii), where () is the mass function over a set (), the set of the consequences that action could lead to;(iv) is a utility function; that is, , where is the set of real numbers.

Then, based on the concept of mass functions, the point-valued expected utility formula can be extended to the context of ambiguity by defining the notion called expected utility interval [25].

Definition 3. Given an ambiguity decision problem , for action , its expected utility interval is given by , where
We cannot obtain a complete preference ordering from an expected utility interval. To address the problem, we can employ a well-known decision rule called the Hurwicz criterion [21], which is given as follows: where the pointed value is called the generalized expected utility or payoff of action and the index can be interpreted as a degree of optimism, which reflects a decision attitude. Particularly, If , then the decision attitude is optimistic. In contrast, the decision attitude is pessimistic if . And the decision attitude is neutral if .

More specifically, the Hurwicz criterion says that, for each action, a decision maker takes a weighted average of the purely optimistic and purely pessimistic value by the degree of optimism. In particular, if , then . This means that the decision maker has a purely pessimistic attitude and chooses the alternative that has the best worst. This strategy is often called the maximin strategy. In contrast, if , then . This means that the decision maker has a purely optimistic attitude and selects the action that has the best best. This strategy is often called the maximax strategy.

Using this criterion, the preference can then be determined as

It is easy to see that the preference ordering defined as (5) is complete.

3. Game Definition

This section presents a new game-theoretic framework for games with ambiguous consequences and then introduces a solution concept for solving such games.

Intuitively, games with ambiguous consequences are designed to depict cases where players only know that the possible consequences of each strategy profile lie in a certain set. For example, Table 1 is the payoff matrix of a game, where is the set of possible consequences associated with the strategy profile for player . However, players are not sure which one of the consequence will occur and also what the probability of each consequence is. More precisely, for each strategy profile, the players can only use a mass function, rather than a probability measure, defined over the set of possible consequences to represent ambiguity concerning consequences. In particular, if mass functions are simple (see Definition 1), then the players are only required to determine the lower probability of some possible consequences within that set. In order to obtain the generalized expected utilities and a complete preference ordering, players need to assign a degree of optimism for each strategy profile. We can then formally define an ambiguous game as follows.

Definition 4. An ambiguous game denoted as is a tuple , where(i) is a set of natural numbers, which denotes the set of players of the game;(ii), where denotes a finite set of pure strategies (or actions) for player ;(iii), where is the set of possible consequences associated with the pure strategy profile for player ;(iv), where is the simple mass function over associated with the pure strategy profile for player ;(v), where is the degree of optimism associated with the pure strategy profile for player ;(vi), where denotes the payoff function of player from the set of the all consequences to the set of real numbers; that is, .

Given an ambiguous game, each player needs to compute the expected payoff interval associated with a pure strategy profile according to formulas (3). By applying the Hurwicz criterion, we can obtain the generalized expected payoffs of profiles. In particular, we have the following result.

Lemma 5. Given an ambiguous game , suppose that, for any pure strategy profile , , , , and . Let , , , and , and let be the generalized expected utility of the pure strategy profile . Then,

Proof. Since player has simple support function , by formulas (3), the lower and upper expected payoffs of profile given mass function are given as follows: By formula (4), we obtain the generalized expected utility of profile for player as formula (6), which establishes the required result.

The above lemma provides a way to calculate associated with any pure strategy profile in an ambiguous game where mass functions are simple. In particular, if is a vacuous mass function, that is, , then, by formula (6), we obtain that In addition, if is a pseudovacuous mass function, that is, , then we have It thus follows that we can transform an ambiguous game into a strategic game defined by classic game theory [27, 28]. As such, we can derive a normal form game with precise payoffs from an ambiguous game. More precisely, given an ambiguous game we can turn it into a strategic game , where and .

Definition 6. Given an ambiguous game , a strategic game, denoted by (since by formula (6), the payoff depends on and ), is called an induced game of , if the element of its payoff matrix is obtained by using formula (6) based on .

As usual, a mixed strategy for player is defined as a probability distribution over the pure strategy set . We denote as the probability assigned by the mixed strategy to player ’s pure strategy . Let be player ’s generalized expected payoff given by the mixed-strategy profile . A pure strategy can then be regarded as a degenerate case of a mixed strategy, in which that pure strategy is assigned with probability 1.

Given an ambiguous game and a mixed-strategy profile , we can compute player ’s generalized expected payoff to as follows: where is the element of and is given by (6).

Definition 7. A mixed-strategy profile in the ambiguous game is an ambiguous mixed-strategy equilibrium, if for all , for every mixed-strategy of player , .

Theorem 8. Given ambiguous game , suppose that is an ambiguous mixed-strategy equilibrium of game . Then is an ambiguous equilibrium of if and only if is a mixed-strategy Nash equilibrium of its induced game .

Proof. By Definition 6 and formula (10), for any mixed-strategy profile , we have that where is player ’s expected payoff given by mixed-strategy profile in game . Let be a mixed-strategy Nash equilibrium of game . Then, for any , we have This implies that, for any , we have Then, according to Definition 7, the mixed-strategy profile is an ambiguous equilibrium of .
If is an ambiguous equilibrium of , then we can show that is also a mixed-strategy Nash equilibrium of in a similar way.

Recall from the well-known result proved by Nash that there always exists at least one mixed-strategy Nash equilibrium for any finite game [28]. It follows immediately from Theorem 8 that any ambiguous game has at least one ambiguous equilibrium, since its induced game has at least one Nash equilibrium.

Essentially, Theorem 8 provides an approach to find the ambiguous mixed-strategy equilibria of an ambiguous game. Given an ambiguous game, we can obtain the induced game with focal mass values using formulas (6) and (10) and then find the mixed-strategy Nash equilibria of the induced game, which are also the ambiguous mixed-strategy equilibria of the original ambiguous game. In this sense, we can find ambiguous mixed strategy equilibria when focal mass values are given. Therefore, the set of ambiguous mixed-strategy equilibria can be regarded as a value of a function, where the variables are the focal mass values.

It is worth noting that in our model players’ payoffs are allowed to be ambiguous, while the traditional games always assume precise payoffs. Within our framework, the point-valued payoffs in the induced game are computed from an interval-valued payoff of the original ambiguous game. Nevertheless, our approach can capture the idea of ambiguity aversion under interactive situations, which is a missing feature of the traditional game-theoretic approaches.

Next, we study how the focused masses may influence the outcomes (solutions) of an ambiguous game. Suppose that every focal mass value in Theorem 8 is an unknown variable. The following theorem demonstrates how to find the maximum value of function given a mixed-strategy profile.

Theorem 9. Given an ambiguous game , suppose that , , , , and . Let , , , and . Given a mixed-strategy profile , let be player ’s generalized expected utility to . Moreover, define as follows: Then, the following assertions hold:(i)if , then function is strictly increasing in the coordinate ;(ii)if , then the function is strictly decreasing in the coordinate ;(iii)if , then the function is independent of the coordinate ;(iv)the function has its maximum at , where

Proof. Firstly, we show that . Since , we have or , which implies that .
For any mixed-strategy profile , by formulas (6) and (10), we have Let Clearly, is linear.
If , then In this case, is strictly increasing, and thus is also strictly increasing in the coordinate .
If , then In this case, is strictly decreasing, and accordingly is strictly decreasing in the coordinate as well.
Finally, if , then which means that is independent of the coordinate . In this case, , and thus we have
Since function is linear, has its maximum if each achieves its maximum. Thus, the function has its maximum at , where , if , if , and , where , if .

As shown in Theorem 9, we have established the relationship between focal mass values, optimistic attitudes, and the generalized expected payoffs given by any mixed-strategy profile. As a result, this theorem demonstrates what a player should do under an ambiguous interactive situation, where he/she only needs to decide his/her  -values and degree of optimism. More specifically, item (i) shows that, for any player , if is more than his/her corresponding degrees of optimism , then the bigger the focal mass value (i.e., the less ambiguity), the bigger the generalized expected payoff and thus the better for player . In contrast, item (ii) indicates that, if is less than his/her corresponding degrees of optimism , then the more ambiguity the better for player . And item (iii) says that if is equal to his/her corresponding degrees of optimism , then player could assign any focal mass value for the focal element of mass function . In addition, item (iv) identifies the conditions under which function has a maximum value.

It is important to note that Theorem 9 holds for any mixed-strategy profile. In light of these results, it seems reasonable to say that there is a close relationship between the focal mass values and the equilibria of an ambiguous game (to find the equilibria of an ambiguous game, players’ focal mass values and degrees of optimism are required to be common knowledge among players; however, Theorem 9 holds even if a player only knows his/her own mass values and degrees of optimism).

The generalized expected utility is calculated according to the Hurwicz criterion, which depends on the attitude of player in an ambiguous game.

Corollary 10. Under the conditions given in Theorem 9, the following assertions hold:(i)if , and player switches from his/her to , , then , where ;(ii)if , and player switches from his/her to , , then , where .

Proof. Since , by item (ii) of Theorem 9, function is strictly decreasing in the coordinate . This means that the smaller the focal mass value, the bigger the generalized expected payoff to any mixed-strategy profile. Thus, as a rational player, player will try to get less information so that he/she will obtain a bigger generalized expected payoff. That is, we have . On the other hand, since , by item (i) of Theorem 9, function is strictly increasing in the coordinate . So, we have . This completes the proof of item (i). Similarly, we can establish item (ii).

Corollary 10 investigates what happens when a player is too optimistic or pessimistic about a strategy profile. If and player switches from his/her to with , then player is too optimistic. In contrast, if if and player switches from his/her to with , then we say that player is too pessimistic. The corollary shows that any player’s generalized expected payoff will be decreasing if he/she is too optimistic or pessimistic.

4. Example: A Defending and Attacking Game

In this section, we illustrate our game-theoretic framework using a strategic situation between a defender and an attacker (both could be a team).

4.1. Problem Description

In this problem, the attacker needs to allocate his/her available resources, for example, personnel and weapons, to attack some targets chosen from three international airports in a country, while the defender needs to allocate his available resources to prevent attacks. Suppose that the possible attack effects or consequences can be divided into 11 different scales from the 1st one being the best attack effect (denoted by ) to the 11th one being the worst attack effect (denoted by ). Clearly, the attacker’s preference ranking over the set of the possible attack effects or consequences is from to , while the defender’s preference ranking over that set is reversed.

Moreover, suppose that there are two kinds of information available in this case. First, public information is known by both the defender and the attacker, such as the average passenger flows, the architectures, the flight schedules of these three airports, the regular safety inspections, and ordinary defending and attacking methods. By contrast, private information of one player might not be available to his opponent. For example, special defending and attacking resources can be regarded as private information, such as irregular patrols, special attacking methods and skills, and the allocation of attackers. In addition, there are some random factors in the game environment that might have impact on the attack effects, which are not controlled by neither the defender nor the attacker during the possible attacks, such as the cooperation abilities of related departments to deal with emergences, the defending skills of unarmed people, and the weather.

As such, it seems unrealistic for both the defender and the attacker to specify the exact consequence (or precise payoff) of a pure strategy profile. Nevertheless, based upon public information and relevant knowledge, they are certain that the possible consequences of each pure strategy profile lie in a set of , a subset of the set of all the possible attack effects. Due to limited information, the defender and the attacker can only identify the lower probabilities (the focal mass values), rather than exact probabilities, of some possible consequences of the pure strategy profile . Furthermore, given such mass values, they both hold an optimistic attitude for each pure strategy profile that determines a generalized expected payoff under the profile.

4.2. Game Model

In this case, we write the pure strategies of the defender and the attacker as , , and , which mean that the defender and the attacker use their full resources to prevent and attack the airports , , and , respectively. According to public information, the ambiguity concerning consequences of each pure strategy profile is represented by a simple mass function for the defender and for the attacker.

By applying Definition 4, this interactive situation can then be modeled as an ambiguous game of , where(i) is the player set, where player 1 is the defender and player 2 is the attacker;(ii) is the pure strategy set, where ;(iii) is the consequence set, where and are the sets of attack effects given pure strategy profile , which are given as row 3 in Tables 2 and 3, respectively, and , where is an attack effect, ;(iv) is the mass function set, where , , and are simple mass functions over and , and the focal elements are and with focal mass values and , respectively. That is, and , ; for instance, according to public information and relevant knowledge, (), (), and () are given by row 2, row 3, and row 4 in Table 2 (Table 3), respectively;(v) is the optimistic attitude set, where and are given by row 6 in Tables 2 and 3, respectively;(vi) is the payoff function set, where and , where ; clearly, does reflect the defender’s preference ordering , and reflects the attacker’s preference ordering .

Given the above setting, -values can be calculated as follows. Since , , , and , we have

Thus, by formula (14), we have

Similarly, we can calculate the other -values for both players, which are given in row 5 of Tables 2 and 3.

4.3. Ambiguous Equilibrium

To find the ambiguous equilibria of this game, let us first compute the expected utility intervals of the pure strategy profile. Take the pure strategy profile as an example. By formulas (7), we can calculate the lower and upper bound of the expected payoff interval for as

In this ambiguous game , we associate the pure strategy profile with the expected payoff interval for player 1. Similarly, we can obtain the expected payoff intervals associated with the other pure strategy profiles, which are all shown in Table 4.

By formula (6), we thus obtain the payoff matrix of induced game (as shown in Table 5).

In this ambiguous game, a mixed strategy (where ) can be interpreted as the defender or attacker allocating proportion of his available resources to prevent or attack airport (). Let be a mixed-strategy profile. Given the induced game , we have

Let and (). Then, we have , , , and . One can easily verify that the strategy profile is the unique mixed-strategy equilibrium of induced game . According to Theorem 8, is also the only ambiguous equilibrium of the ambiguous game . Given this equilibrium point, it follows from formulas (25) that and .

4.4. Relation between Focal Mass Values and Solutions

This subsection illustrates the relationship between the focal mass values and the solutions of an ambiguous game, and how to manage private information under such a situation.

In the above analysis, each focused mass is given as a constant. Now, assume that all the focused masses are variables. Then, according to Theorem 9 and values in row 5 and values in row 6 of Table 2, for the defender and any mixed-strategy profile , we have the following.(i)Since and , the function is strictly increasing in the coordinates and . This means that the more the information represented by , () the better for the defender.(ii)Since , , , and , the function is strictly decreasing in the coordinates , , , and . This means that the less information represented by (, , and ) the better for the defender.(iii)Since , , and , the function is independent of the coordinates , , and .(iv)The function has its maximum value at point , where .Similarly, for the attacker and any mixed-strategy profile , the function achieves its maximum value at point , where .

Given these critical points, we can compute the lower and upper expected payoffs for each pure strategy profile using formulas (7). Thus, we obtain by formula (6) the payoff matrix of the induced game as shown in Table 6. It is easy to show that is the unique mixed-strategy equilibrium of induced game . Thus, by Theorem 8, is the unique ambiguous mixed-strategy equilibrium of the ambiguous game . Given this equilibrium point, we can obtain and , which are the maximums of the defender’s and attacker’s expected payoffs given by the equilibria of the ambiguous game. Indeed, we have that and .

In order to provide a geometric illustration, let us consider a special case that is helpful in demonstrating the relation between the mass value and the ambiguous equilibrium. Let and be two variables, and let the other focused masses be constants as those shown in Table 2. Since and , by item (iv) of Theorem 9, the function achieves its maximum value at the critical point . In view of this, we obtain that the mixed-strategy profile is the ambiguous equilibrium with maximum value . Figure 1 depicts the relation between the focal mass values , , and . One can observe from the figure that the function is strictly increasing in the coordinate and is strictly decreasing in the coordinate .

5. Discussion

In the literature, the Bayesian game [11] is widely used to model interactive situations under ambiguity. Basically, the framework of Bayesian games assumes that a player’s belief regarding the other players’ types is accurate. In other words, it is assumed that the player has a precise probability distribution over the set of the types. In particular, the player should assign an equal probability to each type in the case of complete ignorance. In this framework, the expected payoff of each strategy profile can be computed, and thus a preference ordering can be determined. However, many researches [2, 3, 24] have shown that the belief of a decision maker may not be representable by a precise probability distribution when ambiguity occurs. In contrast, our model employs Dempster-Shafer theory, an instance of theories of imprecise probability, to model ambiguity and thus relaxes the fundamental assumption of Bayesian games.

The Choquet expected utility theory is a natural extension of the expected utility theory to decision making under ambiguity. To deal with ambiguity in games, some papers [1418] apply the Choquet expected utility theory to the context of games, which leads to a Choquet expected payoff for each strategy profile. In these approaches, the players maximize the Choquet expected payoffs, from which a preference ordering can be determined. It is worth pointing out that these approaches assume the consequence of a strategy profile to be determinate. By contrast, our model relaxes such an assumption. Another problem with these approaches is that their solutions, called equilibria in games, may not exist in some cases [29]. However, we have established that there is at least one ambiguous equilibrium in any ambiguous game.

Based on the Choquet expected utility theory, Marinacci [17] studies the ambiguous games by considering pessimism and optimism towards ambiguity, which are two different kinds of extreme attitudes. Unlike his framework, our model resolves ambiguity using the Hurwicz criterion, which is a weighted average of the purely optimistic and purely pessimistic value according to the degree of optimism. As shown in Corollary 10, each player’s outcomes will become worse if he/she is too optimistic or pessimistic. In order to model ambiguity in games, researchers [30, 31] use the model of multiple priors (a set of probabilities) to represent players’ beliefs and employ the maximin decision rule to determine a preference ordering. Such a decision rule requires the decision maker to choose an option that maximizes the minimal expected utilities with respect to the set of multiple priors. Based on these ideas, they provide some analysis for games where players’ beliefs are modeled by multiple priors. As a matter of fact, the Hurwicz criterion is much more general in comparison with the maximin decision rule. Therefore, our game model based on the Hurwicz criterion enables us to investigate how different kinds of attitudes towards ambiguity may affect the solutions of an ambiguous game.

6. Conclusion

In real life, we often need to make decisions under uncertainty. In particular, we may not have sufficient evidence to determine a precise probability distribution over the set of possible consequences of a choice. In this paper, we have provided a new decision-theoretic framework for decision making under uncertainty by applying Dempster-Shafer theory to model ambiguity and the Hurwicz criterion to determine a preference ordering. Based on this decision-theoretic framework, we have developed a game-theoretic model for analyzing games where players may be ambiguous about consequences of some strategy profile. In order to determine the outcomes of such games, we have proposed a new solution concept called ambiguous equilibrium. We have also studied in this paper how players’ optimistic attitudes and their beliefs about the consequences may influence the possible solutions of an ambiguous game. Moreover, we have shown that overly optimistic or pessimistic attitude would make players’ expected payoff worse in ambiguous games.

There are some interesting projects that deserve further investigation. One natural future project is to study the consequences of applying our theory to extensive form games and cooperative games. One can consider Dempster’s rule of combination as the rule for updating based on new information in ambiguous games. It also seems natural to investigate the consistency of the optimistic attitudes that different players have towards the same strategy profile. Finally, another important project for future work is to find some simple algorithm for solving an ambiguous game.

Conflict of Interests

The author declares that there is no conflict of interests regarding the publication of this paper.

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank Matthias Troffaes, Hailin Liu, Xudong Luo, Gert de Cooman, and Teddy Seidenfeld for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper. The author is also extremely grateful to Guiomar Martin-Herran and three referees for their insightful comments, which have significantly improved the paper. This paper is supported by National Fund of Philosophy and Social Science from China (no. 11BZX060), and major projects of National Fund of Philosophy and Social Science from China (no. 13 & ZD186).